Difference between revisions of "Directory:Jon Awbrey/Papers/Differential Logic"

MyWikiBiz, Author Your Legacy — Thursday November 14, 2024
Jump to navigationJump to search
(→‎Note 13: markup)
 
(46 intermediate revisions by the same user not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
 
{{DISPLAYTITLE:Differential Logic}}
 
{{DISPLAYTITLE:Differential Logic}}
'''Differential logic''' is the component of logic whose object is the description of variation for example, the aspects of change, difference, distribution, and diversity in [[universes of discourse]] that are subject to logical description.  In formal logic, differential logic treats the principles that govern the use of a ''differential logical calculus'', that is, a formal system with the expressive capacity to describe change and diversity in logical universes of discourse.
+
<center><font color="red" size="4">
 +
'''&#9734; The MathJax formatter is currently having problems rendering the text below. &#9734;'''<br>
 +
'''&#9734; Meanwhile, please see the InterSciWiki copy at [http://intersci.ss.uci.edu/wiki/index.php/Differential_Logic_:_Sketch_2 Differential Logic : Sketch 2]. &#9734;'''
 +
</font></center>
 +
 
 +
'''Author: [[User:Jon Awbrey|Jon Awbrey]]'''
 +
 
 +
'''Note.'''  ''The present Sketch is largely superseded by the article &ldquo;[[Differential Logic : Introduction]]&rdquo; but I have preserved it here for the sake of the remaining ideas that have yet to be absorbed elsewhere.''
 +
 
 +
'''Differential logic''' is the component of logic whose object is the description of variation &mdash; for example, the aspects of change, difference, distribution, and diversity &mdash; in [[universes of discourse]] that are subject to logical description.  In formal logic, differential logic treats the principles that govern the use of a ''differential logical calculus'', that is, a formal system with the expressive capacity to describe change and diversity in logical universes of discourse.
  
 
A simple example of a differential logical calculus is furnished by a ''[[differential propositional calculus]]''.  A differential propositional calculus is a [[propositional calculus]] extended by a set of terms for describing aspects of change and difference, for example, processes that take place in a universe of discourse or transformations that map a source universe into a target universe.  This augments ordinary propositional calculus in the same way that the differential calculus of Leibniz and Newton augments the analytic geometry of Descartes.
 
A simple example of a differential logical calculus is furnished by a ''[[differential propositional calculus]]''.  A differential propositional calculus is a [[propositional calculus]] extended by a set of terms for describing aspects of change and difference, for example, processes that take place in a universe of discourse or transformations that map a source universe into a target universe.  This augments ordinary propositional calculus in the same way that the differential calculus of Leibniz and Newton augments the analytic geometry of Descartes.
Line 10: Line 19:
 
Now there are many ways to dance around this idea, and I feel like I have tried them all, before one gets down to acting on it, and there many issues of interpretation and justification that we will have to clear up after the fact, that is, before we can be sure that it all really makes any sense, but I think this time I'll just jump in, and show you the form in which this idea first came to me.
 
Now there are many ways to dance around this idea, and I feel like I have tried them all, before one gets down to acting on it, and there many issues of interpretation and justification that we will have to clear up after the fact, that is, before we can be sure that it all really makes any sense, but I think this time I'll just jump in, and show you the form in which this idea first came to me.
  
Start with a proposition of the form <math>x ~\operatorname{and}~ y,</math> which is graphed as two labels attached to a root node:
+
Start with a proposition of the form <math>x ~\mathrm{and}~ y,\!</math> which is graphed as two labels attached to a root node:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
| align="center" |
+
|
 
<pre>
 
<pre>
 
o---------------------------------------o
 
o---------------------------------------o
Line 26: Line 35:
 
|}
 
|}
  
Written as a string, this is just the concatenation "<math>x~y</math>".
+
Written as a string, this is just the concatenation "<math>x~y\!</math>".
  
The proposition <math>xy\!</math> may be taken as a boolean function <math>f(x, y)\!</math> having the abstract type <math>f : \mathbb{B} \times \mathbb{B} \to \mathbb{B},</math> where <math>\mathbb{B} = \{ 0, 1 \}</math> is read in such a way that <math>0\!</math> means <math>\operatorname{false}</math> and <math>1\!</math> means <math>\operatorname{true}.</math>
+
The proposition <math>xy\!</math> may be taken as a boolean function <math>f(x, y)\!</math> having the abstract type <math>f : \mathbb{B} \times \mathbb{B} \to \mathbb{B},\!</math> where <math>\mathbb{B} = \{ 0, 1 \}~\!</math> is read in such a way that <math>0\!</math> means <math>\mathrm{false}\!</math> and <math>1\!</math> means <math>\mathrm{true}.\!</math>
  
In this style of graphical representation, the value <math>\operatorname{true}</math> looks like a blank label and the value <math>\operatorname{false}</math> looks like an edge.
+
In this style of graphical representation, the value <math>\mathrm{true}\!</math> looks like a blank label and the value <math>\mathrm{false}\!</math> looks like an edge.
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
| align="center" |
+
|
 
<pre>
 
<pre>
 
o---------------------------------------o
 
o---------------------------------------o
Line 46: Line 55:
 
|}
 
|}
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
| align="center" |
+
|
 
<pre>
 
<pre>
 
o---------------------------------------o
 
o---------------------------------------o
Line 61: Line 70:
 
|}
 
|}
  
Back to the proposition <math>xy.\!</math>  Imagine yourself standing
+
Back to the proposition <math>xy.~\!</math>  Imagine yourself standing in a fixed cell of the corresponding venn diagram, say, the cell where the proposition <math>xy\!</math> is true, as shown here:
in a fixed cell of the corresponding venn diagram, say, the cell where the proposition <math>xy\!</math> is true, as shown here:
 
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
 
| [[Image:Venn Diagram X And Y.jpg|500px]]
 
| [[Image:Venn Diagram X And Y.jpg|500px]]
 
|}
 
|}
  
Now ask yourself:  What is the value of the proposition <math>xy\!</math> at a distance of <math>dx\!</math> and <math>dy\!</math> from the cell <math>xy\!</math> where you are standing?
+
Now ask yourself:  What is the value of the proposition <math>xy\!</math> at a distance of <math>\mathrm{d}x\!</math> and <math>\mathrm{d}y\!</math> from the cell <math>xy\!</math> where you are standing?
  
 
Don't think about it &mdash; just compute:
 
Don't think about it &mdash; just compute:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
| align="center" |
+
|
 
<pre>
 
<pre>
 
o---------------------------------------o
 
o---------------------------------------o
Line 89: Line 97:
 
To make future graphs easier to draw in ASCII, I will use devices like '''<code>@=@=@</code>''' and '''<code>o=o=o</code>''' to identify several nodes into one, as in this next redrawing:
 
To make future graphs easier to draw in ASCII, I will use devices like '''<code>@=@=@</code>''' and '''<code>o=o=o</code>''' to identify several nodes into one, as in this next redrawing:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
| align="center" |
+
|
 
<pre>
 
<pre>
 
o---------------------------------------o
 
o---------------------------------------o
Line 107: Line 115:
 
|}
 
|}
  
However you draw it, these expressions follow because the expression <math>x + dx,\!</math> where the plus sign indicates addition in <math>\mathbb{B},</math> that is, addition modulo 2, and thus corresponds to the exclusive disjunction operation in logic, parses to a graph of the following form:
+
However you draw it, these expressions follow because the expression <math>x + \mathrm{d}x,\!</math> where the plus sign indicates addition in <math>\mathbb{B},\!</math> that is, addition modulo 2, and thus corresponds to the exclusive disjunction operation in logic, parses to a graph of the following form:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
| align="center" |
+
|
 
<pre>
 
<pre>
 
o---------------------------------------o
 
o---------------------------------------o
Line 127: Line 135:
 
Next question:  What is the difference between the value of the proposition <math>xy\!</math> "over there" and the value of the proposition <math>xy\!</math> where you are, all expressed as general formula, of course?  Here 'tis:
 
Next question:  What is the difference between the value of the proposition <math>xy\!</math> "over there" and the value of the proposition <math>xy\!</math> where you are, all expressed as general formula, of course?  Here 'tis:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
| align="center" |
+
|
 
<pre>
 
<pre>
 
o---------------------------------------o
 
o---------------------------------------o
Line 152: Line 160:
 
|}
 
|}
  
Oh, I forgot to mention:  Computed over <math>\mathbb{B},</math> plus and minus are the very same operation.  This will make the relationship between the differential and the integral parts of the resulting calculus slightly stranger than usual, but never mind that now.
+
Oh, I forgot to mention:  Computed over <math>\mathbb{B},\!</math> plus and minus are the very same operation.  This will make the relationship between the differential and the integral parts of the resulting calculus slightly stranger than usual, but never mind that now.
  
 
Last question, for now:  What is the value of this expression from your current standpoint, that is, evaluated at the point where <math>xy\!</math> is true?  Well, substituting <math>1\!</math> for <math>x\!</math> and <math>1\!</math> for <math>y\!</math> in the graph amounts to the same thing as erasing those labels:
 
Last question, for now:  What is the value of this expression from your current standpoint, that is, evaluated at the point where <math>xy\!</math> is true?  Well, substituting <math>1\!</math> for <math>x\!</math> and <math>1\!</math> for <math>y\!</math> in the graph amounts to the same thing as erasing those labels:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
| align="center" |
+
|
 
<pre>
 
<pre>
 
o---------------------------------------o
 
o---------------------------------------o
Line 183: Line 191:
 
And this is equivalent to the following graph:
 
And this is equivalent to the following graph:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
| align="center" |
+
|
 
<pre>
 
<pre>
 
o---------------------------------------o
 
o---------------------------------------o
Line 205: Line 213:
 
We have just met with the fact that the differential of the '''''and''''' is the '''''or''''' of the differentials.
 
We have just met with the fact that the differential of the '''''and''''' is the '''''or''''' of the differentials.
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
 
| align="center" |
 
| align="center" |
<math>x ~\operatorname{and}~ y \quad \xrightarrow{~\operatorname{Diff}~} \quad dx ~\operatorname{or}~ dy</math>
+
<math>x ~\mathrm{and}~ y \quad \xrightarrow{~\mathrm{Diff}~} \quad \mathrm{d}x ~\mathrm{or}~ \mathrm{d}y\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
| align="center" |
 
| align="center" |
Line 242: Line 250:
 
|}
 
|}
  
A function like this has an abstract type and a concrete type.  The abstract type is what we invoke when we write things like <math>f : \mathbb{B} \times \mathbb{B} \to \mathbb{B}</math> or <math>f : \mathbb{B}^2 \to \mathbb{B}.</math>  The concrete type takes into account the qualitative dimensions or the "units" of the case, which can be explained as follows.
+
A function like this has an abstract type and a concrete type.  The abstract type is what we invoke when we write things like <math>f : \mathbb{B} \times \mathbb{B} \to \mathbb{B}\!</math> or <math>f : \mathbb{B}^2 \to \mathbb{B}.\!</math>  The concrete type takes into account the qualitative dimensions or the "units" of the case, which can be explained as follows.
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
| Let <math>X\!</math> be the set of values <math>\{ \texttt{(} x \texttt{)},~ x \} ~=~ \{ \operatorname{not}~ x,~ x \}.</math>
+
| Let <math>X\!</math> be the set of values <math>\{ \texttt{(} x \texttt{)},~ x \} ~=~ \{ \mathrm{not}~ x,~ x \}.\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
| Let <math>Y\!</math> be the set of values <math>\{ \texttt{(} y \texttt{)},~ y \} ~=~ \{ \operatorname{not}~ y,~ y \}.</math>
+
| Let <math>Y\!</math> be the set of values <math>\{ \texttt{(} y \texttt{)},~ y \} ~=~ \{ \mathrm{not}~ y,~ y \}.\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
Then interpret the usual propositions about <math>x, y\!</math> as functions of the concrete type <math>f : X \times Y \to \mathbb{B}.</math>
+
Then interpret the usual propositions about <math>x, y\!</math> as functions of the concrete type <math>f : X \times Y \to \mathbb{B}.\!</math>
  
We are going to consider various ''operators'' on these functions.  Here, an operator <math>\operatorname{F}</math> is a function that takes one function <math>f\!</math> into another function <math>\operatorname{F}f.</math>
+
We are going to consider various ''operators'' on these functions.  Here, an operator <math>\mathrm{F}\!</math> is a function that takes one function <math>f\!</math> into another function <math>\mathrm{F}f.\!</math>
  
 
The first couple of operators that we need to consider are logical analogues of those that occur in the classical ''finite difference calculus'', namely:
 
The first couple of operators that we need to consider are logical analogues of those that occur in the classical ''finite difference calculus'', namely:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
| The ''difference operator'' <math>\Delta,\!</math> written here as <math>\operatorname{D}.</math>
+
| The ''difference operator'' <math>\Delta,\!</math> written here as <math>\mathrm{D}.\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
| The ''enlargement" operator'' <math>\Epsilon,\!</math> written here as <math>\operatorname{E}.</math>
+
| The ''enlargement" operator'' <math>\Epsilon,\!</math> written here as <math>\mathrm{E}.\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
These days, <math>\operatorname{E}</math> is more often called the ''shift operator''.
+
These days, <math>\mathrm{E}\!</math> is more often called the ''shift operator''.
  
In order to describe the universe in which these operators operate, it is necessary to enlarge the original universe of discourse, passing from the space <math>U = X \times Y</math> to its ''differential extension'', <math>\operatorname{E}U,</math> that has the following description:
+
In order to describe the universe in which these operators operate, it is necessary to enlarge the original universe of discourse, passing from the space <math>U = X \times Y\!</math> to its ''differential extension'', <math>\mathrm{E}U,\!</math> that has the following description:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
| <math>\operatorname{E}U ~=~ U \times \operatorname{d}U ~=~ X \times Y \times \operatorname{d}X \times \operatorname{d}Y,</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{E}U ~=~ U \times \mathrm{d}U ~=~ X \times Y \times \mathrm{d}X \times \mathrm{d}Y,\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
 
with
 
with
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
| <math>\operatorname{d}X = \{ \texttt{(} \operatorname{d}x \texttt{)}, \operatorname{d}x \}</math> &nbsp;and&nbsp; <math>\operatorname{d}Y = \{ \texttt{(} \operatorname{d}y \texttt{)}, \operatorname{d}y \}.</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{d}X = \{ \texttt{(} \mathrm{d}x \texttt{)}, \mathrm{d}x \}\!</math> &nbsp;and&nbsp; <math>\mathrm{d}Y = \{ \texttt{(} \mathrm{d}y \texttt{)}, \mathrm{d}y \}.\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
The interpretations of these new symbols can be diverse, but the easiest
+
The interpretations of these new symbols can be diverse, but the easiest option for now is just to say that <math>\mathrm{d}x\!</math> means "change <math>x\!</math>" and <math>\mathrm{d}y\!</math> means "change <math>y\!</math>".  To draw the differential extension <math>\mathrm{E}U~\!</math> of our present universe <math>U = X \times Y\!</math> as a venn diagram, it would take us four logical dimensions <math>X, Y, \mathrm{d}X, \mathrm{d}Y,\!</math> but we can project a suggestion of what it's about on the universe <math>X \times Y\!</math> by drawing arrows that cross designated borders, labeling the arrows as
option for now is just to say that <math>\operatorname{d}x</math> means "change <math>x\!</math>" and <math>\operatorname{d}y</math> means "change <math>y\!</math>".  To draw the differential extension <math>\operatorname{E}U</math> of our present universe <math>U = X \times Y</math> as a venn diagram, it would take us four logical dimensions <math>X, Y, \operatorname{d}X, \operatorname{d}Y,</math> but we can project a suggestion of what it's about on the universe <math>X \times Y</math> by drawing arrows that cross designated borders, labeling the arrows as
+
<math>\mathrm{d}x\!</math> when crossing the border between <math>x\!</math> and <math>\texttt{(} x \texttt{)}\!</math> and as <math>\mathrm{d}y\!</math> when crossing the border between <math>y\!</math> and <math>\texttt{(} y \texttt{)},\!</math> in either direction, in either case.
<math>\operatorname{d}x</math> when crossing the border between <math>x\!</math> and <math>\texttt{(} x \texttt{)}</math> and as <math>\operatorname{d}y</math> when crossing the border between <math>y\!</math> and <math>\texttt{(} y \texttt{)},</math> in either direction, in either case.
 
  
 
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
 
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
Line 284: Line 291:
 
|}
 
|}
  
Propositions can be formed on differential variables, or any combination of ordinary logical variables and differential logical variables, in all the same ways that propositions can be formed on ordinary logical variables alone.  For instance, the proposition <math>\texttt{(} \operatorname{d}x \texttt{(} \operatorname{d}y \texttt{))}</math> may be read to say that <math>\operatorname{d}x \Rightarrow \operatorname{d}y,</math> in other words, there is "no change in <math>x\!</math> without a change in <math>y\!</math>".
+
Propositions can be formed on differential variables, or any combination of ordinary logical variables and differential logical variables, in all the same ways that propositions can be formed on ordinary logical variables alone.  For instance, the proposition <math>\texttt{(} \mathrm{d}x \texttt{(} \mathrm{d}y \texttt{))}\!</math> may be read to say that <math>\mathrm{d}x \Rightarrow \mathrm{d}y,\!</math> in other words, there is "no change in <math>x\!</math> without a change in <math>y\!</math>".
  
Given the proposition <math>f(x, y)\!</math> in <math>U = X \times Y,</math> the (first order) ''enlargement'' of <math>f\!</math> is the proposition <math>\operatorname{E}f</math> in <math>\operatorname{E}U</math> that is defined by the formula <math>\operatorname{E}f(x, y, \operatorname{d}x, \operatorname{d}y) = f(x + \operatorname{d}x, y + \operatorname{d}y).</math>
+
Given the proposition <math>f(x, y)\!</math> in <math>U = X \times Y,\!</math> the (first order) ''enlargement'' of <math>f\!</math> is the proposition <math>\mathrm{E}f\!</math> in <math>\mathrm{E}U~\!</math> that is defined by the formula <math>\mathrm{E}f(x, y, \mathrm{d}x, \mathrm{d}y) = f(x + \mathrm{d}x, y + \mathrm{d}y).\!</math>
  
Applying the enlargement operator <math>\operatorname{E}</math> to the present example, <math>f(x, y) = xy,\!</math> we may compute the result as follows:
+
Applying the enlargement operator <math>\mathrm{E}\!</math> to the present example, <math>f(x, y) = xy,\!</math> we may compute the result as follows:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
 
| align="center" |
 
| align="center" |
<math>\operatorname{E}f(x, y, \operatorname{d}x, \operatorname{d}y) \quad = \quad (x + \operatorname{d}x)(y + \operatorname{d}y).</math>
+
<math>\mathrm{E}f(x, y, \mathrm{d}x, \mathrm{d}y) \quad = \quad (x + \mathrm{d}x)(y + \mathrm{d}y).\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
| align="center" |
 
| align="center" |
Line 311: Line 318:
 
|}
 
|}
  
Given the proposition <math>f(x, y)\!</math> in <math>U = X \times Y,</math> the (first order) ''difference'' of <math>f\!</math> is the proposition <math>\operatorname{D}f</math> in <math>\operatorname{E}U</math> that is defined by the formula <math>\operatorname{D}f = \operatorname{E}f - f,</math> that is, <math>\operatorname{D}f(x, y, \operatorname{d}x, \operatorname{d}y) = f(x + \operatorname{d}x, y + \operatorname{d}y) - f(x, y).</math>
+
Given the proposition <math>f(x, y)\!</math> in <math>U = X \times Y,\!</math> the (first order) ''difference'' of <math>f\!</math> is the proposition <math>\mathrm{D}f~\!</math> in <math>\mathrm{E}U~\!</math> that is defined by the formula <math>\mathrm{D}f = \mathrm{E}f - f,\!</math> that is, <math>\mathrm{D}f(x, y, \mathrm{d}x, \mathrm{d}y) = f(x + \mathrm{d}x, y + \mathrm{d}y) - f(x, y).\!</math>
  
 
In the example <math>f(x, y) = xy,\!</math> the result is:
 
In the example <math>f(x, y) = xy,\!</math> the result is:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
 
| align="center" |
 
| align="center" |
<math>\operatorname{D}f(x, y, \operatorname{d}x, \operatorname{d}y) \quad = \quad (x + \operatorname{d}x)(y + \operatorname{d}y) - xy.</math>
+
<math>\mathrm{D}f(x, y, \mathrm{d}x, \mathrm{d}y) \quad = \quad (x + \mathrm{d}x)(y + \mathrm{d}y) - xy.\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
| align="center" |
 
| align="center" |
Line 343: Line 350:
 
|}
 
|}
  
We did not yet go through the trouble to interpret this (first order) ''difference of conjunction'' fully, but were happy simply to evaluate it with respect to a single location in the universe of discourse, namely, at the point picked out by the singular proposition <math>xy,\!</math> that is, at the place where <math>x = 1\!</math> and <math>y = 1.\!</math>  This evaluation is written in the form <math>\operatorname{D}f|_{xy}</math> or <math>\operatorname{D}f|_{(1, 1)},</math> and we arrived at the locally applicable law that is stated and illustrated as follows:
+
We did not yet go through the trouble to interpret this (first order) ''difference of conjunction'' fully, but were happy simply to evaluate it with respect to a single location in the universe of discourse, namely, at the point picked out by the singular proposition <math>xy,\!</math> that is, at the place where <math>x = 1\!</math> and <math>y = 1.\!</math>  This evaluation is written in the form <math>\mathrm{D}f|_{xy}\!</math> or <math>\mathrm{D}f|_{(1, 1)},\!</math> and we arrived at the locally applicable law that is stated and illustrated as follows:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
 
| align="center" |
 
| align="center" |
<math>f(x, y) ~=~ xy ~=~ x ~\operatorname{and}~ y \quad \Rightarrow \quad \operatorname{D}f|_{xy} ~=~ \texttt{((} \operatorname{dx} \texttt{)(} \operatorname{d}y \texttt{))} ~=~ \operatorname{d}x ~\operatorname{or}~ \operatorname{d}y.</math>
+
<math>f(x, y) ~=~ xy ~=~ x ~\mathrm{and}~ y \quad \Rightarrow \quad \mathrm{D}f|_{xy} ~=~ \texttt{((} \mathrm{dx} \texttt{)(} \mathrm{d}y \texttt{))} ~=~ \mathrm{d}x ~\mathrm{or}~ \mathrm{d}y.\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
| align="center" | [[Image:Venn Diagram Difference Conj At Conj.jpg|500px]]
 
| align="center" | [[Image:Venn Diagram Difference Conj At Conj.jpg|500px]]
Line 354: Line 361:
 
|}
 
|}
  
The picture shows the analysis of the inclusive disjunction <math>\texttt{((} \operatorname{d}x \texttt{)(} \operatorname{d}y \texttt{))}</math> into the following exclusive disjunction:
+
The picture shows the analysis of the inclusive disjunction <math>\texttt{((} \mathrm{d}x \texttt{)(} \mathrm{d}y \texttt{))}\!</math> into the following exclusive disjunction:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
| align="center" | <math>\operatorname{d}x ~\texttt{(} \operatorname{d}y \texttt{)} ~+~ \operatorname{d}y ~\texttt{(} \operatorname{d}x \texttt{)} ~+~ \operatorname{d}x ~\operatorname{d}y.</math>
+
| align="center" | <math>\mathrm{d}x ~\texttt{(} \mathrm{d}y \texttt{)} ~+~ \mathrm{d}y ~\texttt{(} \mathrm{d}x \texttt{)} ~+~ \mathrm{d}x ~\mathrm{d}y.\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
Line 364: Line 371:
 
==Note 3==
 
==Note 3==
  
Last time we computed what will variously be called the ''difference map'', the ''difference proposition'', or the ''local proposition'' <math>\operatorname{D}f_p</math> for the proposition <math>f(x, y) = xy\!</math> at the point <math>p\!</math> where <math>x = 1\!</math> and <math>y = 1.\!</math>
+
Last time we computed what will variously be called the ''difference map'', the ''difference proposition'', or the ''local proposition'' <math>\mathrm{D}f_p\!</math> for the proposition <math>f(x, y) = xy\!</math> at the point <math>p\!</math> where <math>x = 1\!</math> and <math>y = 1.\!</math>
  
In the universe <math>U = X \times Y,</math> the four propositions <math>xy,~ x\texttt{(}y\texttt{)},~ \texttt{(}x\texttt{)}y,~ \texttt{(}x\texttt{)(}y\texttt{)}</math> that indicate the "cells", or the smallest regions of the venn diagram, are called ''singular propositions''.  These serve as an alternative notation for naming the points <math>(1, 1),~ (1, 0),~ (0, 1),~ (0, 0),\!</math> respectively.
+
In the universe <math>U = X \times Y,\!</math> the four propositions <math>xy,~ x\texttt{(}y\texttt{)},~ \texttt{(}x\texttt{)}y,~ \texttt{(}x\texttt{)(}y\texttt{)}\!</math> that indicate the "cells", or the smallest regions of the venn diagram, are called ''singular propositions''.  These serve as an alternative notation for naming the points <math>(1, 1),~ (1, 0),~ (0, 1),~ (0, 0),\!</math> respectively.
  
Thus we can write <math>\operatorname{D}f_p = \operatorname{D}f|p = \operatorname{D}f|(1, 1) = \operatorname{D}f|xy,</math> so long as we know the frame of reference in force.
+
Thus we can write <math>\mathrm{D}f_p = \mathrm{D}f|p = \mathrm{D}f|(1, 1) = \mathrm{D}f|xy,\!</math> so long as we know the frame of reference in force.
  
Sticking with the example <math>f(x, y) = xy,\!</math> let us compute the value of the difference proposition <math>\operatorname{D}f</math> at all 4 points.
+
Sticking with the example <math>f(x, y) = xy,\!</math> let us compute the value of the difference proposition <math>\mathrm{D}f~\!</math> at all 4 points.
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
 
| align="center" |
 
| align="center" |
 
<pre>
 
<pre>
Line 494: Line 501:
 
The easy way to visualize the values of these graphical expressions is just to notice the following equivalents:
 
The easy way to visualize the values of these graphical expressions is just to notice the following equivalents:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
 
| align="center" |
 
| align="center" |
 
<pre>
 
<pre>
Line 541: Line 548:
 
|}
 
|}
  
The Figure shows the points of the extended universe <math>\operatorname{E}U = X \times Y \times \operatorname{d}X \times \operatorname{d}Y</math> that satisfy the difference proposition <math>\operatorname{D}f,</math> namely, these:
+
The Figure shows the points of the extended universe <math>\mathrm{E}U = X \times Y \times \mathrm{d}X \times \mathrm{d}Y\!</math> that satisfy the difference proposition <math>\mathrm{D}f,\!</math> namely, these:
  
 
{| align="center" cellpadding="6"
 
{| align="center" cellpadding="6"
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{array}{rcccc}
 
<math>\begin{array}{rcccc}
1. &  x  &  y  &  \operatorname{d}x  &  \operatorname{d}y
+
1. &  x  &  y  &  \mathrm{d}x  &  \mathrm{d}y
 
\\
 
\\
2. &  x  &  y  &  \operatorname{d}x  & (\operatorname{d}y)
+
2. &  x  &  y  &  \mathrm{d}x  & (\mathrm{d}y)
 
\\
 
\\
3. &  x  &  y  & (\operatorname{d}x) &  \operatorname{d}y
+
3. &  x  &  y  & (\mathrm{d}x) &  \mathrm{d}y
 
\\
 
\\
4. &  x  & (y) & (\operatorname{d}x) &  \operatorname{d}y
+
4. &  x  & (y) & (\mathrm{d}x) &  \mathrm{d}y
 
\\
 
\\
5. & (x) &  y  &  \operatorname{d}x  & (\operatorname{d}y)
+
5. & (x) &  y  &  \mathrm{d}x  & (\mathrm{d}y)
 
\\
 
\\
6. & (x) & (y) &  \operatorname{d}x  &  \operatorname{d}y
+
6. & (x) & (y) &  \mathrm{d}x  &  \mathrm{d}y
\end{array}</math>
+
\end{array}\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
An inspection of these six points should make it easy to understand <math>\operatorname{D}f</math> as telling you what you have to do from each point of <math>U\!</math> in order to change the value borne by the proposition <math>f(x, y).\!</math>
+
An inspection of these six points should make it easy to understand <math>\mathrm{D}f~\!</math> as telling you what you have to do from each point of <math>U\!</math> in order to change the value borne by the proposition <math>f(x, y).\!</math>
  
 
==Note 4==
 
==Note 4==
  
We have been studying the action of the difference operator <math>\operatorname{D},</math> also known as the ''localization operator'', on the proposition <math>f : X \times Y \to \mathbb{B}</math> that is commonly known as the conjunction <math>x \cdot y.</math>  We described <math>\operatorname{D}f</math> as a (first order) differential proposition, that is, a proposition of the type <math>\operatorname{D}f : X \times Y \times \operatorname{d}X \times \operatorname{d}Y \to \mathbb{B}.</math>  Abstracting from the augmented venn diagram that illustrates how the ''models'' or ''satisfying interpretations'' of <math>\operatorname{D}f</math> distribute within the extended universe <math>\operatorname{E}U = X \times Y \times \operatorname{d}X \times \operatorname{d}Y,</math> we can depict <math>\operatorname{D}f</math> in the form of a ''digraph'' or ''directed graph'', one whose points are labeled with the elements of <math>U =  X \times Y</math> and whose arrows are labeled with the elements of <math>\operatorname{d}U = \operatorname{d}X \times \operatorname{d}Y.</math>
+
We have been studying the action of the difference operator <math>\mathrm{D},\!</math> also known as the ''localization operator'', on the proposition <math>f : X \times Y \to \mathbb{B}\!</math> that is commonly known as the conjunction <math>x \cdot y.\!</math>  We described <math>\mathrm{D}f~\!</math> as a (first order) differential proposition, that is, a proposition of the type <math>\mathrm{D}f : X \times Y \times \mathrm{d}X \times \mathrm{d}Y \to \mathbb{B}.\!</math>  Abstracting from the augmented venn diagram that illustrates how the ''models'' or ''satisfying interpretations'' of <math>\mathrm{D}f~\!</math> distribute within the extended universe <math>\mathrm{E}U = X \times Y \times \mathrm{d}X \times \mathrm{d}Y,\!</math> we can depict <math>\mathrm{D}f~\!</math> in the form of a ''digraph'' or ''directed graph'', one whose points are labeled with the elements of <math>U =  X \times Y\!</math> and whose arrows are labeled with the elements of <math>\mathrm{d}U = \mathrm{d}X \times \mathrm{d}Y.\!</math>
  
 
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
 
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
Line 576: Line 583:
 
& = & x  & \cdot & y
 
& = & x  & \cdot & y
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{D}f
+
\mathrm{D}f
& = &  x  & \cdot &  y  & \cdot & ((\operatorname{d}x)(\operatorname{d}y))
+
& = &  x  & \cdot &  y  & \cdot & ((\mathrm{d}x)(\mathrm{d}y))
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
& + &  x  & \cdot & (y) & \cdot & ~(\operatorname{d}x)~\operatorname{d}y~~
+
& + &  x  & \cdot & (y) & \cdot & ~(\mathrm{d}x)~\mathrm{d}y~~
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
& + & (x) & \cdot &  y  & \cdot & ~~\operatorname{d}x~(\operatorname{d}y)~
+
& + & (x) & \cdot &  y  & \cdot & ~~\mathrm{d}x~(\mathrm{d}y)~
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
& + & (x) & \cdot & (y) & \cdot & ~~\operatorname{d}x~~\operatorname{d}y~~
+
& + & (x) & \cdot & (y) & \cdot & ~~\mathrm{d}x~~\mathrm{d}y~~
\end{array}</math>
+
\end{array}\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
Line 591: Line 598:
 
==Note 5==
 
==Note 5==
  
The ''enlargement'' or ''shift'' operator <math>\operatorname{E}</math> exhibits a wealth of interesting and useful properties in its own right, so it pays to examine a few of the more salient features that play out on the surface of our initial example, <math>f(x, y) = xy.\!</math>
+
The ''enlargement'' or ''shift'' operator <math>\mathrm{E}\!</math> exhibits a wealth of interesting and useful properties in its own right, so it pays to examine a few of the more salient features that play out on the surface of our initial example, <math>f(x, y) = xy.\!</math>
  
 
A suitably generic definition of the extended universe of discourse is afforded by the following set-up:
 
A suitably generic definition of the extended universe of discourse is afforded by the following set-up:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{array}{ccclll}
 
<math>\begin{array}{ccclll}
Line 602: Line 609:
 
X_1 \times \ldots \times X_k.
 
X_1 \times \ldots \times X_k.
 
\\[6pt]
 
\\[6pt]
\text{Let}  & \operatorname{d}U
+
\text{Let}  & \mathrm{d}U
 
& = &
 
& = &
\operatorname{d}X_1 \times \ldots \times \operatorname{d}X_k.
+
\mathrm{d}X_1 \times \ldots \times \mathrm{d}X_k.
 
\\[6pt]
 
\\[6pt]
\text{Then} & \operatorname{E}U
+
\text{Then} & \mathrm{E}U
 
& = &
 
& = &
X_1 \times \ldots \times X_k ~\times~ \operatorname{d}X_1 \times \ldots \times \operatorname{d}X_k
+
X_1 \times \ldots \times X_k ~\times~ \mathrm{d}X_1 \times \ldots \times \mathrm{d}X_k
 
& = &
 
& = &
U \times \operatorname{d}U.
+
U \times \mathrm{d}U.
\end{array}</math>
+
\end{array}\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
For a proposition of the form <math>f : X_1 \times \ldots \times X_k \to \mathbb{B},</math> the (first order) ''enlargement'' of <math>f\!</math> is the proposition <math>\operatorname{E}f : \operatorname{E}U \to \mathbb{B}</math> that is defined by the following equation:
+
For a proposition of the form <math>f : X_1 \times \ldots \times X_k \to \mathbb{B},\!</math> the (first order) ''enlargement'' of <math>f\!</math> is the proposition <math>\mathrm{E}f : \mathrm{E}U \to \mathbb{B}\!</math> that is defined by the following equation:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
| <math>\operatorname{E}f(x_1, \ldots, x_k, \operatorname{d}x_1, \ldots, \operatorname{d}x_k) ~=~ f(x_1 + \operatorname{d}x_1, \ldots, x_k + \operatorname{d}x_k).</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{E}f(x_1, \ldots, x_k, \mathrm{d}x_1, \ldots, \mathrm{d}x_k) ~=~ f(x_1 + \mathrm{d}x_1, \ldots, x_k + \mathrm{d}x_k).\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
The ''differential variables'' <math>\operatorname{d}x_j</math> are boolean variables of the same basic type as the ordinary variables <math>x_j.\!</math>  It is conventional to distinguish the (first order) differential variables with the operative prefix "<math>\operatorname{d}</math>", but this is purely optional.  It is their existence in particular relations to the initial variables, not their names, that defines them as differential variables.
+
The ''differential variables'' <math>\mathrm{d}x_j\!</math> are boolean variables of the same basic type as the ordinary variables <math>x_j.\!</math>  It is conventional to distinguish the (first order) differential variables with the operative prefix "<math>\mathrm{d}\!</math>", but this is purely optional.  It is their existence in particular relations to the initial variables, not their names, that defines them as differential variables.
  
In the case of logical conjunction, <math>f(x, y) = xy,\!</math> the computation of the enlargement <math>\operatorname{E}f</math> begins as follows:
+
In the case of logical conjunction, <math>f(x, y) = xy,\!</math> the computation of the enlargement <math>\mathrm{E}f\!</math> begins as follows:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
| <math>\operatorname{E}f(x, y, \operatorname{d}x, \operatorname{d}y) ~=~ (x + \operatorname{d}x)(y + \operatorname{d}y).</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{E}f(x, y, \mathrm{d}x, \mathrm{d}y) ~=~ (x + \mathrm{d}x)(y + \mathrm{d}y).\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
Given that this expression uses nothing more than the ''boolean ring'' operations of addition <math>(+)\!</math> and multiplication <math>(\cdot),</math> it is permissible to multiply things out in the usual manner to arrive at the following result:
+
Given that this expression uses nothing more than the ''boolean ring'' operations of addition <math>(+)\!</math> and multiplication <math>(\cdot),\!</math> it is permissible to multiply things out in the usual manner to arrive at the following result:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
| <math>\operatorname{E}f(x, y, \operatorname{d}x, \operatorname{d}y) ~=~ x~y ~+~ x~\operatorname{d}y ~+~ y~\operatorname{d}x ~+~ \operatorname{d}x~\operatorname{d}y.</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{E}f(x, y, \mathrm{d}x, \mathrm{d}y) ~=~ x~y ~+~ x~\mathrm{d}y ~+~ y~\mathrm{d}x ~+~ \mathrm{d}x~\mathrm{d}y.\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
To understand what this means in logical terms, it is useful to go back and analyze the above expression for <math>\operatorname{E}f</math> in the same way that we did for <math>\operatorname{D}f.</math>  Toward that end, the next set of Figures represent the computation of the ''enlarged'' or ''shifted'' proposition <math>\operatorname{E}f</math> at each of the 4 points in the universe of discourse <math>U = X \times Y.</math>
+
To understand what this means in logical terms, it is useful to go back and analyze the above expression for <math>\mathrm{E}f\!</math> in the same way that we did for <math>\mathrm{D}f.\!</math>  Toward that end, the next set of Figures represent the computation of the ''enlarged'' or ''shifted'' proposition <math>\mathrm{E}f\!</math> at each of the 4 points in the universe of discourse <math>U = X \times Y.\!</math>
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
 
| align="center" |
 
| align="center" |
 
<pre>
 
<pre>
Line 721: Line 728:
 
|}
 
|}
  
Given the sort of data that arises from this form of analysis, we can now fold the disjoined ingredients back into a boolean expansion or a DNF that is equivalent to the proposition <math>\operatorname{E}f.</math>
+
Given the sort of data that arises from this form of analysis, we can now fold the disjoined ingredients back into a boolean expansion or a DNF that is equivalent to the proposition <math>\mathrm{E}f.\!</math>
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
| <math>\operatorname{E}f ~~=~~ xy \cdot \operatorname{E}f_{xy} ~~+~~ x(y) \cdot \operatorname{E}f_{x(y)} ~~+~~ (x)y \cdot \operatorname{E}f_{(x)y} ~~+~~ (x)(y) \cdot \operatorname{E}f_{(x)(y)}.</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{E}f ~~=~~ xy \cdot \mathrm{E}f_{xy} ~~+~~ x(y) \cdot \mathrm{E}f_{x(y)} ~~+~~ (x)y \cdot \mathrm{E}f_{(x)y} ~~+~~ (x)(y) \cdot \mathrm{E}f_{(x)(y)}.\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
Here is a summary of the result, illustrated by means of a digraph picture, where the "no change" element <math>(\operatorname{d}x)(\operatorname{d}y)</math> is drawn as a loop at the point <math>x~y.</math>
+
Here is a summary of the result, illustrated by means of a digraph picture, where the "no change" element <math>(\mathrm{d}x)(\mathrm{d}y)\!</math> is drawn as a loop at the point <math>x~y.\!</math>
  
 
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
 
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
Line 739: Line 746:
 
& = & x  & \cdot & y
 
& = & x  & \cdot & y
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{E}f
+
\mathrm{E}f
& = &  x  & \cdot &  y  & \cdot & (\operatorname{d}x)(\operatorname{d}y)
+
& = &  x  & \cdot &  y  & \cdot & (\mathrm{d}x)(\mathrm{d}y)
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
& + &  x  & \cdot & (y) & \cdot & (\operatorname{d}x)~\operatorname{d}y~
+
& + &  x  & \cdot & (y) & \cdot & (\mathrm{d}x)~\mathrm{d}y~
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
& + & (x) & \cdot &  y  & \cdot & ~\operatorname{d}x~(\operatorname{d}y)
+
& + & (x) & \cdot &  y  & \cdot & ~\mathrm{d}x~(\mathrm{d}y)
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
& + & (x) & \cdot & (y) & \cdot & ~\operatorname{d}x~~\operatorname{d}y~\end{array}</math>
+
& + & (x) & \cdot & (y) & \cdot & ~\mathrm{d}x~~\mathrm{d}y~\end{array}\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
We may understand the enlarged proposition <math>\operatorname{E}f</math> as telling us all the different ways to reach a model of the proposition <math>f\!</math> from each point of the universe <math>U.\!</math>
+
We may understand the enlarged proposition <math>\mathrm{E}f\!</math> as telling us all the different ways to reach a model of the proposition <math>f\!</math> from each point of the universe <math>U.\!</math>
  
 
==Note 6==
 
==Note 6==
  
To broaden our experience with simple examples, let us examine the sixteen functions of concrete type <math>X \times Y \to \mathbb{B}</math> and abstract type <math>\mathbb{B} \times \mathbb{B} \to \mathbb{B}.</math>  A few Tables are set here that detail the actions of <math>\operatorname{E}</math> and <math>\operatorname{D}</math> on each of these functions, allowing us to view the results in several different ways.
+
To broaden our experience with simple examples, let us examine the sixteen functions of concrete type <math>X \times Y \to \mathbb{B}\!</math> and abstract type <math>\mathbb{B} \times \mathbb{B} \to \mathbb{B}.\!</math>  A few Tables are set here that detail the actions of <math>\mathrm{E}\!</math> and <math>\mathrm{D}\!</math> on each of these functions, allowing us to view the results in several different ways.
  
 
Tables A1 and A2 show two ways of arranging the 16 boolean functions on two variables, giving equivalent expressions for each function in several different systems of notation.
 
Tables A1 and A2 show two ways of arranging the 16 boolean functions on two variables, giving equivalent expressions for each function in several different systems of notation.
Line 760: Line 767:
  
 
{| align="center" border="1" cellpadding="8" cellspacing="0" style="background:#f8f8ff; text-align:center; width:90%"
 
{| align="center" border="1" cellpadding="8" cellspacing="0" style="background:#f8f8ff; text-align:center; width:90%"
|+ <math>\text{Table A1.}~~\text{Propositional Forms on Two Variables}</math>
+
|+ <math>\text{Table A1.}~~\text{Propositional Forms on Two Variables}\!</math>
 
|- style="background:#f0f0ff"
 
|- style="background:#f0f0ff"
 
| width="15%" |
 
| width="15%" |
<p><math>\mathcal{L}_1</math></p>
+
<p><math>\mathcal{L}_1\!</math></p>
<p><math>\text{Decimal}</math></p>
+
<p><math>\text{Decimal}\!</math></p>
 
| width="15%" |
 
| width="15%" |
<p><math>\mathcal{L}_2</math></p>
+
<p><math>\mathcal{L}_2\!</math></p>
<p><math>\text{Binary}</math></p>
+
<p><math>\text{Binary}\!</math></p>
 
| width="15%" |
 
| width="15%" |
<p><math>\mathcal{L}_3</math></p>
+
<p><math>\mathcal{L}_3\!</math></p>
<p><math>\text{Vector}</math></p>
+
<p><math>\text{Vector}\!</math></p>
 
| width="15%" |
 
| width="15%" |
<p><math>\mathcal{L}_4</math></p>
+
<p><math>\mathcal{L}_4\!</math></p>
<p><math>\text{Cactus}</math></p>
+
<p><math>\text{Cactus}\!</math></p>
 
| width="25%" |
 
| width="25%" |
<p><math>\mathcal{L}_5</math></p>
+
<p><math>\mathcal{L}_5\!</math></p>
<p><math>\text{English}</math></p>
+
<p><math>\text{English}\!</math></p>
 
| width="15%" |
 
| width="15%" |
<p><math>\mathcal{L}_6</math></p>
+
<p><math>\mathcal{L}_6~\!</math></p>
<p><math>\text{Ordinary}</math></p>
+
<p><math>\text{Ordinary}\!</math></p>
 
|- style="background:#f0f0ff"
 
|- style="background:#f0f0ff"
 
| &nbsp;
 
| &nbsp;
Line 812: Line 819:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_7
 
f_7
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 830: Line 837:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_{0111}
 
f_{0111}
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 848: Line 855:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
0~1~1~1
 
0~1~1~1
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 857: Line 864:
 
(x)~y~
 
(x)~y~
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
(x)~~~
+
(x)[[User:Jon Awbrey|Jon Awbrey]] ([[User talk:Jon Awbrey|talk]])
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~x~(y)
 
~x~(y)
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
~~~(y)
+
[[User:Jon Awbrey|Jon Awbrey]] ([[User talk:Jon Awbrey|talk]])(y)
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
(x,~y)
 
(x,~y)
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
(x~~y)
 
(x~~y)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 884: Line 891:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
\text{not both}~ x ~\text{and}~ y
 
\text{not both}~ x ~\text{and}~ y
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 902: Line 909:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
\lnot x \lor \lnot y
 
\lnot x \lor \lnot y
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
|
 
|
Line 921: Line 928:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_{15}
 
f_{15}
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 939: Line 946:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_{1111}
 
f_{1111}
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 957: Line 964:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
1~1~1~1
 
1~1~1~1
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 964: Line 971:
 
((x,~y))
 
((x,~y))
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
~~~~~y~~
+
16:08, 11 December 2014 (UTC)y~~
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~(x~(y))
 
~(x~(y))
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
~~x~~~~~
+
~~x16:08, 11 December 2014 (UTC)
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
((x)~y)~
 
((x)~y)~
Line 975: Line 982:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
((~))
 
((~))
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 993: Line 1,000:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
\text{true}
 
\text{true}
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,011: Line 1,018:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
1
 
1
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
Line 1,017: Line 1,024:
  
 
{| align="center" border="1" cellpadding="8" cellspacing="0" style="background:#f8f8ff; text-align:center; width:90%"
 
{| align="center" border="1" cellpadding="8" cellspacing="0" style="background:#f8f8ff; text-align:center; width:90%"
|+ <math>\text{Table A2.}~~\text{Propositional Forms on Two Variables}</math>
+
|+ <math>\text{Table A2.}~~\text{Propositional Forms on Two Variables}\!</math>
 
|- style="background:#f0f0ff"
 
|- style="background:#f0f0ff"
 
| width="15%" |
 
| width="15%" |
<p><math>\mathcal{L}_1</math></p>
+
<p><math>\mathcal{L}_1\!</math></p>
<p><math>\text{Decimal}</math></p>
+
<p><math>\text{Decimal}\!</math></p>
 
| width="15%" |
 
| width="15%" |
<p><math>\mathcal{L}_2</math></p>
+
<p><math>\mathcal{L}_2\!</math></p>
<p><math>\text{Binary}</math></p>
+
<p><math>\text{Binary}\!</math></p>
 
| width="15%" |
 
| width="15%" |
<p><math>\mathcal{L}_3</math></p>
+
<p><math>\mathcal{L}_3\!</math></p>
<p><math>\text{Vector}</math></p>
+
<p><math>\text{Vector}\!</math></p>
 
| width="15%" |
 
| width="15%" |
<p><math>\mathcal{L}_4</math></p>
+
<p><math>\mathcal{L}_4\!</math></p>
<p><math>\text{Cactus}</math></p>
+
<p><math>\text{Cactus}\!</math></p>
 
| width="25%" |
 
| width="25%" |
<p><math>\mathcal{L}_5</math></p>
+
<p><math>\mathcal{L}_5\!</math></p>
<p><math>\text{English}</math></p>
+
<p><math>\text{English}\!</math></p>
 
| width="15%" |
 
| width="15%" |
<p><math>\mathcal{L}_6</math></p>
+
<p><math>\mathcal{L}_6~\!</math></p>
<p><math>\text{Ordinary}</math></p>
+
<p><math>\text{Ordinary}\!</math></p>
 
|- style="background:#f0f0ff"
 
|- style="background:#f0f0ff"
 
| &nbsp;
 
| &nbsp;
Line 1,054: Line 1,061:
 
| <math>f_0\!</math>
 
| <math>f_0\!</math>
 
| <math>f_{0000}\!</math>
 
| <math>f_{0000}\!</math>
| <math>0~0~0~0</math>
+
| <math>0~0~0~0\!</math>
| <math>(~)</math>
+
| <math>(~)\!</math>
 
| <math>\text{false}\!</math>
 
| <math>\text{false}\!</math>
 
| <math>0\!</math>
 
| <math>0\!</math>
Line 1,068: Line 1,075:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_8
 
f_8
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,078: Line 1,085:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_{1000}
 
f_{1000}
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,088: Line 1,095:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
1~0~0~0
 
1~0~0~0
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,098: Line 1,105:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~x~~y~
 
~x~~y~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,108: Line 1,115:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
x ~\text{and}~ y
 
x ~\text{and}~ y
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,118: Line 1,125:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
x \land y
 
x \land y
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
|
 
|
Line 1,125: Line 1,132:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_{12}
 
f_{12}
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,131: Line 1,138:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_{1100}
 
f_{1100}
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,137: Line 1,144:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
1~1~0~0
 
1~1~0~0
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,143: Line 1,150:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~x~
 
~x~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,149: Line 1,156:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
x
 
x
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,155: Line 1,162:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
x
 
x
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
|
 
|
Line 1,162: Line 1,169:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_9
 
f_9
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,168: Line 1,175:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_{1001}
 
f_{1001}
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,174: Line 1,181:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
1~0~0~1
 
1~0~0~1
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,180: Line 1,187:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
((x,~y))
 
((x,~y))
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,186: Line 1,193:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
x ~\text{equal to}~ y
 
x ~\text{equal to}~ y
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,192: Line 1,199:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
x = y
 
x = y
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
|
 
|
Line 1,199: Line 1,206:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_{10}
 
f_{10}
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,205: Line 1,212:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_{1010}
 
f_{1010}
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,211: Line 1,218:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
1~0~1~0
 
1~0~1~0
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,217: Line 1,224:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~y~
 
~y~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,223: Line 1,230:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
y
 
y
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,229: Line 1,236:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
y
 
y
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
|
 
|
Line 1,240: Line 1,247:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_{14}
 
f_{14}
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,250: Line 1,257:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_{1110}
 
f_{1110}
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,260: Line 1,267:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
1~1~1~0
 
1~1~1~0
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,270: Line 1,277:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
((x)(y))
 
((x)(y))
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,280: Line 1,287:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
x ~\text{or}~ y
 
x ~\text{or}~ y
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,290: Line 1,297:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
x \lor y
 
x \lor y
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
| <math>f_{15}\!</math>
 
| <math>f_{15}\!</math>
 
| <math>f_{1111}\!</math>
 
| <math>f_{1111}\!</math>
| <math>1~1~1~1</math>
+
| <math>1~1~1~1\!</math>
| <math>((~))</math>
+
| <math>((~))\!</math>
 
| <math>\text{true}\!</math>
 
| <math>\text{true}\!</math>
 
| <math>1\!</math>
 
| <math>1\!</math>
Line 1,302: Line 1,309:
 
<br>
 
<br>
  
The next four Tables expand the expressions of <math>\operatorname{E}f</math> and <math>\operatorname{D}f</math> in two different ways, for each of the sixteen functions.  Notice that the functions are given in a different order, here being collected into a set of seven natural classes.
+
The next four Tables expand the expressions of <math>\mathrm{E}f\!</math> and <math>\mathrm{D}f~\!</math> in two different ways, for each of the sixteen functions.  Notice that the functions are given in a different order, here being collected into a set of seven natural classes.
  
 
<br>
 
<br>
  
 
{| align="center" border="1" cellpadding="8" cellspacing="0" style="background:#f8f8ff; text-align:center; width:90%"
 
{| align="center" border="1" cellpadding="8" cellspacing="0" style="background:#f8f8ff; text-align:center; width:90%"
|+ <math>\text{Table A3.}~~\operatorname{E}f ~\text{Expanded Over Differential Features}~ \{ \operatorname{d}x, \operatorname{d}y \}</math>
+
|+ <math>\text{Table A3.}~~\mathrm{E}f ~\text{Expanded Over Differential Features}~ \{ \mathrm{d}x, \mathrm{d}y \}\!</math>
 
|- style="background:#f0f0ff"
 
|- style="background:#f0f0ff"
 
| width="10%" | &nbsp;
 
| width="10%" | &nbsp;
 
| width="18%" | <math>f\!</math>
 
| width="18%" | <math>f\!</math>
 
| width="18%" |  
 
| width="18%" |  
<p><math>\operatorname{T}_{11} f</math></p>
+
<p><math>\mathrm{T}_{11} f\!</math></p>
<p><math>\operatorname{E}f|_{\operatorname{d}x~\operatorname{d}y}</math></p>
+
<p><math>\mathrm{E}f|_{\mathrm{d}x~\mathrm{d}y}\!</math></p>
 
| width="18%" |
 
| width="18%" |
<p><math>\operatorname{T}_{10} f</math></p>
+
<p><math>\mathrm{T}_{10} f\!</math></p>
<p><math>\operatorname{E}f|_{\operatorname{d}x(\operatorname{d}y)}</math></p>
+
<p><math>\mathrm{E}f|_{\mathrm{d}x(\mathrm{d}y)}\!</math></p>
 
| width="18%" |
 
| width="18%" |
<p><math>\operatorname{T}_{01} f</math></p>
+
<p><math>\mathrm{T}_{01} f\!</math></p>
<p><math>\operatorname{E}f|_{(\operatorname{d}x)\operatorname{d}y}</math></p>
+
<p><math>\mathrm{E}f|_{(\mathrm{d}x)\mathrm{d}y}\!</math></p>
 
| width="18%" |
 
| width="18%" |
<p><math>\operatorname{T}_{00} f</math></p>
+
<p><math>\mathrm{T}_{00} f\!</math></p>
<p><math>\operatorname{E}f|_{(\operatorname{d}x)(\operatorname{d}y)}</math></p>
+
<p><math>\mathrm{E}f|_{(\mathrm{d}x)(\mathrm{d}y)}\!</math></p>
 
|-
 
|-
 
| <math>f_0\!</math>
 
| <math>f_0\!</math>
| <math>(~)</math>
+
| <math>(~)\!</math>
| <math>(~)</math>
+
| <math>(~)\!</math>
| <math>(~)</math>
+
| <math>(~)\!</math>
| <math>(~)</math>
+
| <math>(~)\!</math>
| <math>(~)</math>
+
| <math>(~)\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
|
 
|
Line 1,340: Line 1,347:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_8
 
f_8
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,350: Line 1,357:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~x~~y~
 
~x~~y~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,360: Line 1,367:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
(x)(y)
 
(x)(y)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,370: Line 1,377:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
(x)~y~
 
(x)~y~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,380: Line 1,387:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~x~(y)
 
~x~(y)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,390: Line 1,397:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~x~~y~
 
~x~~y~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
|
 
|
Line 1,397: Line 1,404:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_{12}
 
f_{12}
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,403: Line 1,410:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~x~
 
~x~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,409: Line 1,416:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
(x)
 
(x)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,415: Line 1,422:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
(x)
 
(x)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,421: Line 1,428:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~x~
 
~x~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,427: Line 1,434:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~x~
 
~x~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
|
 
|
Line 1,434: Line 1,441:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_9
 
f_9
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,440: Line 1,447:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
((x,~y))
 
((x,~y))
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,446: Line 1,453:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
((x,~y))
 
((x,~y))
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,452: Line 1,459:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~(x,~y)~
 
~(x,~y)~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,458: Line 1,465:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~(x,~y)~
 
~(x,~y)~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,464: Line 1,471:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
((x,~y))
 
((x,~y))
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
|
 
|
Line 1,471: Line 1,478:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_{10}
 
f_{10}
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,477: Line 1,484:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~y~
 
~y~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,483: Line 1,490:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
(y)
 
(y)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,489: Line 1,496:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~y~
 
~y~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,495: Line 1,502:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
(y)
 
(y)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,501: Line 1,508:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~y~
 
~y~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
|
 
|
Line 1,512: Line 1,519:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_{14}
 
f_{14}
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,522: Line 1,529:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
((x)(y))
 
((x)(y))
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,532: Line 1,539:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
(~x~~y~)
 
(~x~~y~)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,542: Line 1,549:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
(~x~(y))
 
(~x~(y))
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,552: Line 1,559:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
((x)~y~)
 
((x)~y~)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,562: Line 1,569:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
((x)(y))
 
((x)(y))
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
| <math>f_{15}\!</math>
 
| <math>f_{15}\!</math>
| <math>((~))</math>
+
| <math>((~))\!</math>
| <math>((~))</math>
+
| <math>((~))\!</math>
| <math>((~))</math>
+
| <math>((~))\!</math>
| <math>((~))</math>
+
| <math>((~))\!</math>
| <math>((~))</math>
+
| <math>((~))\!</math>
 
|- style="background:#f0f0ff"
 
|- style="background:#f0f0ff"
 
| colspan="2" | <math>\text{Fixed Point Total}\!</math>
 
| colspan="2" | <math>\text{Fixed Point Total}\!</math>
Line 1,581: Line 1,588:
  
 
{| align="center" border="1" cellpadding="8" cellspacing="0" style="background:#f8f8ff; text-align:center; width:90%"
 
{| align="center" border="1" cellpadding="8" cellspacing="0" style="background:#f8f8ff; text-align:center; width:90%"
|+ <math>\text{Table A4.}~~\operatorname{D}f ~\text{Expanded Over Differential Features}~ \{ \operatorname{d}x, \operatorname{d}y \}</math>
+
|+ <math>\text{Table A4.}~~\mathrm{D}f ~\text{Expanded Over Differential Features}~ \{ \mathrm{d}x, \mathrm{d}y \}\!</math>
 
|- style="background:#f0f0ff"
 
|- style="background:#f0f0ff"
 
| width="10%" | &nbsp;
 
| width="10%" | &nbsp;
 
| width="18%" | <math>f\!</math>
 
| width="18%" | <math>f\!</math>
 
| width="18%" |
 
| width="18%" |
<math>\operatorname{D}f|_{\operatorname{d}x~\operatorname{d}y}</math>
+
<math>\mathrm{D}f|_{\mathrm{d}x~\mathrm{d}y}\!</math>
 
| width="18%" |
 
| width="18%" |
<math>\operatorname{D}f|_{\operatorname{d}x(\operatorname{d}y)}</math>
+
<math>\mathrm{D}f|_{\mathrm{d}x(\mathrm{d}y)}\!</math>
 
| width="18%" |
 
| width="18%" |
<math>\operatorname{D}f|_{(\operatorname{d}x)\operatorname{d}y}</math>
+
<math>\mathrm{D}f|_{(\mathrm{d}x)\mathrm{d}y}\!</math>
 
| width="18%" |
 
| width="18%" |
<math>\operatorname{D}f|_{(\operatorname{d}x)(\operatorname{d}y)}</math>
+
<math>\mathrm{D}f|_{(\mathrm{d}x)(\mathrm{d}y)}\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
| <math>f_0\!</math>
 
| <math>f_0\!</math>
| <math>(~)</math>
+
| <math>(~)\!</math>
| <math>(~)</math>
+
| <math>(~)\!</math>
| <math>(~)</math>
+
| <math>(~)\!</math>
| <math>(~)</math>
+
| <math>(~)\!</math>
| <math>(~)</math>
+
| <math>(~)\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
|
 
|
Line 1,610: Line 1,617:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_8
 
f_8
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,620: Line 1,627:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~x~~y~
 
~x~~y~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,630: Line 1,637:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
((x,~y))
 
((x,~y))
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,640: Line 1,647:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~y~
 
~y~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,650: Line 1,657:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~x~
 
~x~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,660: Line 1,667:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
(~)
 
(~)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
|
 
|
Line 1,667: Line 1,674:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_{12}
 
f_{12}
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,673: Line 1,680:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~x~
 
~x~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,679: Line 1,686:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
((~))
 
((~))
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}~\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,685: Line 1,692:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
((~))
 
((~))
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}~\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,691: Line 1,698:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
(~)
 
(~)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,697: Line 1,704:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
(~)
 
(~)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
|
 
|
Line 1,704: Line 1,711:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_9
 
f_9
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,710: Line 1,717:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
((x,~y))
 
((x,~y))
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,716: Line 1,723:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
(~)
 
(~)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,722: Line 1,729:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
((~))
 
((~))
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}~\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,728: Line 1,735:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
((~))
 
((~))
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}~\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,734: Line 1,741:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
(~)
 
(~)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
|
 
|
Line 1,741: Line 1,748:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_{10}
 
f_{10}
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,747: Line 1,754:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~y~
 
~y~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,753: Line 1,760:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
((~))
 
((~))
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}~\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,759: Line 1,766:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
(~)
 
(~)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,765: Line 1,772:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
((~))
 
((~))
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}~\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,771: Line 1,778:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
(~)
 
(~)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
|
 
|
Line 1,782: Line 1,789:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_{14}
 
f_{14}
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,792: Line 1,799:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
((x)(y))
 
((x)(y))
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,802: Line 1,809:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
((x,~y))
 
((x,~y))
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,812: Line 1,819:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
(y)
 
(y)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,822: Line 1,829:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
(x)
 
(x)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,832: Line 1,839:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
(~)
 
(~)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
| <math>f_{15}\!</math>
 
| <math>f_{15}\!</math>
| <math>((~))</math>
+
| <math>((~))\!</math>
| <math>(~)</math>
+
| <math>(~)\!</math>
| <math>(~)</math>
+
| <math>(~)\!</math>
| <math>(~)</math>
+
| <math>(~)\!</math>
| <math>(~)</math>
+
| <math>(~)\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
Line 1,845: Line 1,852:
  
 
{| align="center" border="1" cellpadding="8" cellspacing="0" style="background:#f8f8ff; text-align:center; width:90%"
 
{| align="center" border="1" cellpadding="8" cellspacing="0" style="background:#f8f8ff; text-align:center; width:90%"
|+ <math>\text{Table A5.}~~\operatorname{E}f ~\text{Expanded Over Ordinary Features}~ \{ x, y \}</math>
+
|+ <math>\text{Table A5.}~~\mathrm{E}f ~\text{Expanded Over Ordinary Features}~ \{ x, y \}\!</math>
 
|- style="background:#f0f0ff"
 
|- style="background:#f0f0ff"
 
| width="10%" | &nbsp;
 
| width="10%" | &nbsp;
 
| width="18%" | <math>f\!</math>
 
| width="18%" | <math>f\!</math>
| width="18%" | <math>\operatorname{E}f|_{xy}</math>
+
| width="18%" | <math>\mathrm{E}f|_{xy}\!</math>
| width="18%" | <math>\operatorname{E}f|_{x(y)}</math>
+
| width="18%" | <math>\mathrm{E}f|_{x(y)}\!</math>
| width="18%" | <math>\operatorname{E}f|_{(x)y}</math>
+
| width="18%" | <math>\mathrm{E}f|_{(x)y}\!</math>
| width="18%" | <math>\operatorname{E}f|_{(x)(y)}</math>
+
| width="18%" | <math>\mathrm{E}f|_{(x)(y)}\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
| <math>f_0\!</math>
 
| <math>f_0\!</math>
| <math>(~)</math>
+
| <math>(~)\!</math>
| <math>(~)</math>
+
| <math>(~)\!</math>
| <math>(~)</math>
+
| <math>(~)\!</math>
| <math>(~)</math>
+
| <math>(~)\!</math>
| <math>(~)</math>
+
| <math>(~)\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
|
 
|
Line 1,870: Line 1,877:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_8
 
f_8
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,880: Line 1,887:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~x~~y~
 
~x~~y~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
~\operatorname{d}x~~\operatorname{d}y~
+
~\mathrm{d}x~~\mathrm{d}y~
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
~\operatorname{d}x~(\operatorname{d}y)
+
~\mathrm{d}x~(\mathrm{d}y)
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
(\operatorname{d}x)~\operatorname{d}y~
+
(\mathrm{d}x)~\mathrm{d}y~
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
(\operatorname{d}x)(\operatorname{d}y)
+
(\mathrm{d}x)(\mathrm{d}y)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
~\operatorname{d}x~(\operatorname{d}y)
+
~\mathrm{d}x~(\mathrm{d}y)
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
~\operatorname{d}x~~\operatorname{d}y~
+
~\mathrm{d}x~~\mathrm{d}y~
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
(\operatorname{d}x)(\operatorname{d}y)
+
(\mathrm{d}x)(\mathrm{d}y)
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
(\operatorname{d}x)~\operatorname{d}y~
+
(\mathrm{d}x)~\mathrm{d}y~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
(\operatorname{d}x)~\operatorname{d}y~
+
(\mathrm{d}x)~\mathrm{d}y~
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
(\operatorname{d}x)(\operatorname{d}y)
+
(\mathrm{d}x)(\mathrm{d}y)
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
~\operatorname{d}x~~\operatorname{d}y~
+
~\mathrm{d}x~~\mathrm{d}y~
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
~\operatorname{d}x~(\operatorname{d}y)
+
~\mathrm{d}x~(\mathrm{d}y)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
(\operatorname{d}x)(\operatorname{d}y)
+
(\mathrm{d}x)(\mathrm{d}y)
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
(\operatorname{d}x)~\operatorname{d}y~
+
(\mathrm{d}x)~\mathrm{d}y~
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
~\operatorname{d}x~(\operatorname{d}y)
+
~\mathrm{d}x~(\mathrm{d}y)
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
~\operatorname{d}x~~\operatorname{d}y~
+
~\mathrm{d}x~~\mathrm{d}y~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
|
 
|
Line 1,927: Line 1,934:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_{12}
 
f_{12}
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,933: Line 1,940:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~x~
 
~x~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
~\operatorname{d}x~
+
~\mathrm{d}x~
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
(\operatorname{d}x)
+
(\mathrm{d}x)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
~\operatorname{d}x~
+
~\mathrm{d}x~
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
(\operatorname{d}x)
+
(\mathrm{d}x)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
(\operatorname{d}x)
+
(\mathrm{d}x)
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
~\operatorname{d}x~
+
~\mathrm{d}x~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
(\operatorname{d}x)
+
(\mathrm{d}x)
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
~\operatorname{d}x~
+
~\mathrm{d}x~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
|
 
|
Line 1,964: Line 1,971:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_9
 
f_9
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 1,970: Line 1,977:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
((x,~y))
 
((x,~y))
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
~(\operatorname{d}x,~\operatorname{d}y)~
+
~(\mathrm{d}x,~\mathrm{d}y)~
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
((\operatorname{d}x,~\operatorname{d}y))
+
((\mathrm{d}x,~\mathrm{d}y))
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}~\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
((\operatorname{d}x,~\operatorname{d}y))
+
((\mathrm{d}x,~\mathrm{d}y))
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
~(\operatorname{d}x,~\operatorname{d}y)~
+
~(\mathrm{d}x,~\mathrm{d}y)~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
((\operatorname{d}x,~\operatorname{d}y))
+
((\mathrm{d}x,~\mathrm{d}y))
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
~(\operatorname{d}x,~\operatorname{d}y)~
+
~(\mathrm{d}x,~\mathrm{d}y)~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
~(\operatorname{d}x,~\operatorname{d}y)~
+
~(\mathrm{d}x,~\mathrm{d}y)~
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
((\operatorname{d}x,~\operatorname{d}y))
+
((\mathrm{d}x,~\mathrm{d}y))
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}~\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
|
 
|
Line 2,001: Line 2,008:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_{10}
 
f_{10}
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 2,007: Line 2,014:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~y~
 
~y~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
~\operatorname{d}y~
+
~\mathrm{d}y~
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
(\operatorname{d}y)
+
(\mathrm{d}y)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
(\operatorname{d}y)
+
(\mathrm{d}y)
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
~\operatorname{d}y~
+
~\mathrm{d}y~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
~\operatorname{d}y~
+
~\mathrm{d}y~
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
(\operatorname{d}y)
+
(\mathrm{d}y)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
(\operatorname{d}y)
+
(\mathrm{d}y)
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
~\operatorname{d}y~
+
~\mathrm{d}y~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
|
 
|
Line 2,042: Line 2,049:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_{14}
 
f_{14}
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 2,052: Line 2,059:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
((x)(y))
 
((x)(y))
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
((\operatorname{d}x)(\operatorname{d}y))
+
((\mathrm{d}x)(\mathrm{d}y))
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
((\operatorname{d}x)~\operatorname{d}y~)
+
((\mathrm{d}x)~\mathrm{d}y~)
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
(~\operatorname{d}x~(\operatorname{d}y))
+
(~\mathrm{d}x~(\mathrm{d}y))
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
(~\operatorname{d}x~~\operatorname{d}y~)
+
(~\mathrm{d}x~~\mathrm{d}y~)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
((\operatorname{d}x)~\operatorname{d}y~)
+
((\mathrm{d}x)~\mathrm{d}y~)
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
((\operatorname{d}x)(\operatorname{d}y))
+
((\mathrm{d}x)(\mathrm{d}y))
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
(~\operatorname{d}x~~\operatorname{d}y~)
+
(~\mathrm{d}x~~\mathrm{d}y~)
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
(~\operatorname{d}x~(\operatorname{d}y))
+
(~\mathrm{d}x~(\mathrm{d}y))
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
(~\operatorname{d}x~(\operatorname{d}y))
+
(~\mathrm{d}x~(\mathrm{d}y))
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
(~\operatorname{d}x~~\operatorname{d}y~)
+
(~\mathrm{d}x~~\mathrm{d}y~)
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
((\operatorname{d}x)(\operatorname{d}y))
+
((\mathrm{d}x)(\mathrm{d}y))
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
((\operatorname{d}x)~\operatorname{d}y~)
+
((\mathrm{d}x)~\mathrm{d}y~)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
(~\operatorname{d}x~~\operatorname{d}y~)
+
(~\mathrm{d}x~~\mathrm{d}y~)
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
(~\operatorname{d}x~(\operatorname{d}y))
+
(~\mathrm{d}x~(\mathrm{d}y))
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
((\operatorname{d}x)~\operatorname{d}y~)
+
((\mathrm{d}x)~\mathrm{d}y~)
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
((\operatorname{d}x)(\operatorname{d}y))
+
((\mathrm{d}x)(\mathrm{d}y))
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
| <math>f_{15}\!</math>
 
| <math>f_{15}\!</math>
| <math>((~))</math>
+
| <math>((~))\!</math>
| <math>((~))</math>
+
| <math>((~))\!</math>
| <math>((~))</math>
+
| <math>((~))\!</math>
| <math>((~))</math>
+
| <math>((~))\!</math>
| <math>((~))</math>
+
| <math>((~))\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
Line 2,105: Line 2,112:
  
 
{| align="center" border="1" cellpadding="8" cellspacing="0" style="background:#f8f8ff; text-align:center; width:90%"
 
{| align="center" border="1" cellpadding="8" cellspacing="0" style="background:#f8f8ff; text-align:center; width:90%"
|+ <math>\text{Table A6.}~~\operatorname{D}f ~\text{Expanded Over Ordinary Features}~ \{ x, y \}</math>
+
|+ <math>\text{Table A6.}~~\mathrm{D}f ~\text{Expanded Over Ordinary Features}~ \{ x, y \}\!</math>
 
|- style="background:#f0f0ff"
 
|- style="background:#f0f0ff"
 
| width="10%" | &nbsp;
 
| width="10%" | &nbsp;
 
| width="18%" | <math>f\!</math>
 
| width="18%" | <math>f\!</math>
| width="18%" | <math>\operatorname{D}f|_{xy}</math>
+
| width="18%" | <math>\mathrm{D}f|_{xy}\!</math>
| width="18%" | <math>\operatorname{D}f|_{x(y)}</math>
+
| width="18%" | <math>\mathrm{D}f|_{x(y)}\!</math>
| width="18%" | <math>\operatorname{D}f|_{(x)y}</math>
+
| width="18%" | <math>\mathrm{D}f|_{(x)y}~\!</math>
| width="18%" | <math>\operatorname{D}f|_{(x)(y)}</math>
+
| width="18%" | <math>\mathrm{D}f|_{(x)(y)}\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
| <math>f_0\!</math>
 
| <math>f_0\!</math>
| <math>(~)</math>
+
| <math>(~)\!</math>
| <math>(~)</math>
+
| <math>(~)\!</math>
| <math>(~)</math>
+
| <math>(~)\!</math>
| <math>(~)</math>
+
| <math>(~)\!</math>
| <math>(~)</math>
+
| <math>(~)\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
|
 
|
Line 2,130: Line 2,137:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_8
 
f_8
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 2,140: Line 2,147:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~x~~y~
 
~x~~y~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
~~\operatorname{d}x~~\operatorname{d}y~~
+
~~\mathrm{d}x~~\mathrm{d}y~~
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
~~\operatorname{d}x~(\operatorname{d}y)~
+
~~\mathrm{d}x~(\mathrm{d}y)~
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
~(\operatorname{d}x)~\operatorname{d}y~~
+
~(\mathrm{d}x)~\mathrm{d}y~~
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
((\operatorname{d}x)(\operatorname{d}y))
+
((\mathrm{d}x)(\mathrm{d}y))
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
~~\operatorname{d}x~(\operatorname{d}y)~
+
~~\mathrm{d}x~(\mathrm{d}y)~
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
~~\operatorname{d}x~~\operatorname{d}y~~
+
~~\mathrm{d}x~~\mathrm{d}y~~
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
((\operatorname{d}x)(\operatorname{d}y))
+
((\mathrm{d}x)(\mathrm{d}y))
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
~(\operatorname{d}x)~\operatorname{d}y~~
+
~(\mathrm{d}x)~\mathrm{d}y~~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
~(\operatorname{d}x)~\operatorname{d}y~~
+
~(\mathrm{d}x)~\mathrm{d}y~~
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
((\operatorname{d}x)(\operatorname{d}y))
+
((\mathrm{d}x)(\mathrm{d}y))
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
~~\operatorname{d}x~~\operatorname{d}y~~
+
~~\mathrm{d}x~~\mathrm{d}y~~
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
~~\operatorname{d}x~(\operatorname{d}y)~
+
~~\mathrm{d}x~(\mathrm{d}y)~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
((\operatorname{d}x)(\operatorname{d}y))
+
((\mathrm{d}x)(\mathrm{d}y))
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
~(\operatorname{d}x)~\operatorname{d}y~~
+
~(\mathrm{d}x)~\mathrm{d}y~~
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
~~\operatorname{d}x~(\operatorname{d}y)~
+
~~\mathrm{d}x~(\mathrm{d}y)~
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
~~\operatorname{d}x~~\operatorname{d}y~~
+
~~\mathrm{d}x~~\mathrm{d}y~~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
|
 
|
Line 2,187: Line 2,194:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_{12}
 
f_{12}
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 2,193: Line 2,200:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~x~
 
~x~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
\operatorname{d}x
+
\mathrm{d}x
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{d}x
+
\mathrm{d}x
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
\operatorname{d}x
+
\mathrm{d}x
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{d}x
+
\mathrm{d}x
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
\operatorname{d}x
+
\mathrm{d}x
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{d}x
+
\mathrm{d}x
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
\operatorname{d}x
+
\mathrm{d}x
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{d}x
+
\mathrm{d}x
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
|
 
|
Line 2,224: Line 2,231:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_9
 
f_9
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 2,230: Line 2,237:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
((x,~y))
 
((x,~y))
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
(\operatorname{d}x,~\operatorname{d}y)
+
(\mathrm{d}x,~\mathrm{d}y)
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
(\operatorname{d}x,~\operatorname{d}y)
+
(\mathrm{d}x,~\mathrm{d}y)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
(\operatorname{d}x,~\operatorname{d}y)
+
(\mathrm{d}x,~\mathrm{d}y)
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
(\operatorname{d}x,~\operatorname{d}y)
+
(\mathrm{d}x,~\mathrm{d}y)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
(\operatorname{d}x,~\operatorname{d}y)
+
(\mathrm{d}x,~\mathrm{d}y)
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
(\operatorname{d}x,~\operatorname{d}y)
+
(\mathrm{d}x,~\mathrm{d}y)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
(\operatorname{d}x,~\operatorname{d}y)
+
(\mathrm{d}x,~\mathrm{d}y)
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
(\operatorname{d}x,~\operatorname{d}y)
+
(\mathrm{d}x,~\mathrm{d}y)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
|
 
|
Line 2,261: Line 2,268:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_{10}
 
f_{10}
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 2,267: Line 2,274:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~y~
 
~y~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
\operatorname{d}y
+
\mathrm{d}y
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{d}y
+
\mathrm{d}y
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
\operatorname{d}y
+
\mathrm{d}y
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{d}y
+
\mathrm{d}y
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
\operatorname{d}y
+
\mathrm{d}y
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{d}y
+
\mathrm{d}y
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
\operatorname{d}y
+
\mathrm{d}y
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{d}y
+
\mathrm{d}y
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
|
 
|
Line 2,302: Line 2,309:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_{14}
 
f_{14}
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 2,312: Line 2,319:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
((x)(y))
 
((x)(y))
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
((\operatorname{d}x)(\operatorname{d}y))
+
((\mathrm{d}x)(\mathrm{d}y))
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
~(\operatorname{d}x)~\operatorname{d}y~~
+
~(\mathrm{d}x)~\mathrm{d}y~~
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
~~\operatorname{d}x~(\operatorname{d}y)~
+
~~\mathrm{d}x~(\mathrm{d}y)~
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
~~\operatorname{d}x~~\operatorname{d}y~~
+
~~\mathrm{d}x~~\mathrm{d}y~~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
~(\operatorname{d}x)~\operatorname{d}y~~
+
~(\mathrm{d}x)~\mathrm{d}y~~
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
((\operatorname{d}x)(\operatorname{d}y))
+
((\mathrm{d}x)(\mathrm{d}y))
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
~~\operatorname{d}x~~\operatorname{d}y~~
+
~~\mathrm{d}x~~\mathrm{d}y~~
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
~~\operatorname{d}x~(\operatorname{d}y)~
+
~~\mathrm{d}x~(\mathrm{d}y)~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
~~\operatorname{d}x~(\operatorname{d}y)~
+
~~\mathrm{d}x~(\mathrm{d}y)~
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
~~\operatorname{d}x~~\operatorname{d}y~~
+
~~\mathrm{d}x~~\mathrm{d}y~~
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
((\operatorname{d}x)(\operatorname{d}y))
+
((\mathrm{d}x)(\mathrm{d}y))
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
~(\operatorname{d}x)~\operatorname{d}y~~
+
~(\mathrm{d}x)~\mathrm{d}y~~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
~~\operatorname{d}x~~\operatorname{d}y~~
+
~~\mathrm{d}x~~\mathrm{d}y~~
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
~~\operatorname{d}x~(\operatorname{d}y)~
+
~~\mathrm{d}x~(\mathrm{d}y)~
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
~(\operatorname{d}x)~\operatorname{d}y~~
+
~(\mathrm{d}x)~\mathrm{d}y~~
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
((\operatorname{d}x)(\operatorname{d}y))
+
((\mathrm{d}x)(\mathrm{d}y))
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
| <math>f_{15}\!</math>
 
| <math>f_{15}\!</math>
| <math>((~))</math>
+
| <math>((~))\!</math>
| <math>((~))</math>
+
| <math>((~))\!</math>
| <math>((~))</math>
+
| <math>((~))\!</math>
| <math>((~))</math>
+
| <math>((~))\!</math>
| <math>((~))</math>
+
| <math>((~))\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
Line 2,368: Line 2,375:
 
==Note 7==
 
==Note 7==
  
If you think that I linger in the realm of logical difference calculus out of sheer vacillation about getting down to the differential proper, it is probably out of a prior expectation that you derive from the art or the long-engrained practice of real analysis.  But the fact is that ordinary calculus only rushes on to the sundry orders of approximation because the strain of comprehending the full import of <math>\operatorname{E}</math> and <math>\operatorname{D}</math> at once whelm over its discrete and finite powers to grasp them.  But here, in the fully serene idylls of ZOL, we find ourselves fit with the compass of a wit that is all we'd ever wish to explore their effects with care.
+
If you think that I linger in the realm of logical difference calculus out of sheer vacillation about getting down to the differential proper, it is probably out of a prior expectation that you derive from the art or the long-engrained practice of real analysis.  But the fact is that ordinary calculus only rushes on to the sundry orders of approximation because the strain of comprehending the full import of <math>\mathrm{E}\!</math> and <math>\mathrm{D}\!</math> at once whelm over its discrete and finite powers to grasp them.  But here, in the fully serene idylls of ZOL, we find ourselves fit with the compass of a wit that is all we'd ever wish to explore their effects with care.
  
 
So let us do just that.
 
So let us do just that.
Line 2,377: Line 2,384:
  
 
{| align="center" border="1" cellpadding="8" cellspacing="0" style="background:#f8f8ff; text-align:center; width:90%"
 
{| align="center" border="1" cellpadding="8" cellspacing="0" style="background:#f8f8ff; text-align:center; width:90%"
|+ <math>\text{Table A3.}~~\operatorname{E}f ~\text{Expanded Over Differential Features}~ \{ \operatorname{d}x, \operatorname{d}y \}</math>
+
|+ <math>\text{Table A3.}~~\mathrm{E}f ~\text{Expanded Over Differential Features}~ \{ \mathrm{d}x, \mathrm{d}y \}\!</math>
 
|- style="background:#f0f0ff"
 
|- style="background:#f0f0ff"
 
| width="10%" | &nbsp;
 
| width="10%" | &nbsp;
 
| width="18%" | <math>f\!</math>
 
| width="18%" | <math>f\!</math>
 
| width="18%" |  
 
| width="18%" |  
<p><math>\operatorname{T}_{11} f</math></p>
+
<p><math>\mathrm{T}_{11} f\!</math></p>
<p><math>\operatorname{E}f|_{\operatorname{d}x~\operatorname{d}y}</math></p>
+
<p><math>\mathrm{E}f|_{\mathrm{d}x~\mathrm{d}y}\!</math></p>
 
| width="18%" |
 
| width="18%" |
<p><math>\operatorname{T}_{10} f</math></p>
+
<p><math>\mathrm{T}_{10} f\!</math></p>
<p><math>\operatorname{E}f|_{\operatorname{d}x(\operatorname{d}y)}</math></p>
+
<p><math>\mathrm{E}f|_{\mathrm{d}x(\mathrm{d}y)}\!</math></p>
 
| width="18%" |
 
| width="18%" |
<p><math>\operatorname{T}_{01} f</math></p>
+
<p><math>\mathrm{T}_{01} f\!</math></p>
<p><math>\operatorname{E}f|_{(\operatorname{d}x)\operatorname{d}y}</math></p>
+
<p><math>\mathrm{E}f|_{(\mathrm{d}x)\mathrm{d}y}\!</math></p>
 
| width="18%" |
 
| width="18%" |
<p><math>\operatorname{T}_{00} f</math></p>
+
<p><math>\mathrm{T}_{00} f\!</math></p>
<p><math>\operatorname{E}f|_{(\operatorname{d}x)(\operatorname{d}y)}</math></p>
+
<p><math>\mathrm{E}f|_{(\mathrm{d}x)(\mathrm{d}y)}\!</math></p>
 
|-
 
|-
 
| <math>f_0\!</math>
 
| <math>f_0\!</math>
| <math>(~)</math>
+
| <math>(~)\!</math>
| <math>(~)</math>
+
| <math>(~)\!</math>
| <math>(~)</math>
+
| <math>(~)\!</math>
| <math>(~)</math>
+
| <math>(~)\!</math>
| <math>(~)</math>
+
| <math>(~)\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
|
 
|
Line 2,410: Line 2,417:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_8
 
f_8
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 2,420: Line 2,427:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~x~~y~
 
~x~~y~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 2,430: Line 2,437:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
(x)(y)
 
(x)(y)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 2,440: Line 2,447:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
(x)~y~
 
(x)~y~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 2,450: Line 2,457:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~x~(y)
 
~x~(y)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 2,460: Line 2,467:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~x~~y~
 
~x~~y~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
|
 
|
Line 2,467: Line 2,474:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_{12}
 
f_{12}
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 2,473: Line 2,480:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~x~
 
~x~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 2,479: Line 2,486:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
(x)
 
(x)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 2,485: Line 2,492:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
(x)
 
(x)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 2,491: Line 2,498:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~x~
 
~x~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 2,497: Line 2,504:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~x~
 
~x~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
|
 
|
Line 2,504: Line 2,511:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_9
 
f_9
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 2,510: Line 2,517:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
((x,~y))
 
((x,~y))
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 2,516: Line 2,523:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
((x,~y))
 
((x,~y))
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 2,522: Line 2,529:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~(x,~y)~
 
~(x,~y)~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 2,528: Line 2,535:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~(x,~y)~
 
~(x,~y)~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 2,534: Line 2,541:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
((x,~y))
 
((x,~y))
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
|
 
|
Line 2,541: Line 2,548:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_{10}
 
f_{10}
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 2,547: Line 2,554:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~y~
 
~y~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 2,553: Line 2,560:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
(y)
 
(y)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 2,559: Line 2,566:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~y~
 
~y~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 2,565: Line 2,572:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
(y)
 
(y)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 2,571: Line 2,578:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
~y~
 
~y~
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
|
 
|
Line 2,582: Line 2,589:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
f_{14}
 
f_{14}
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 2,592: Line 2,599:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
((x)(y))
 
((x)(y))
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 2,602: Line 2,609:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
(~x~~y~)
 
(~x~~y~)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 2,612: Line 2,619:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
(~x~(y))
 
(~x~(y))
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 2,622: Line 2,629:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
((x)~y~)
 
((x)~y~)
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 2,632: Line 2,639:
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
 
((x)(y))
 
((x)(y))
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
| <math>f_{15}\!</math>
 
| <math>f_{15}\!</math>
| <math>((~))</math>
+
| <math>((~))\!</math>
| <math>((~))</math>
+
| <math>((~))\!</math>
| <math>((~))</math>
+
| <math>((~))\!</math>
| <math>((~))</math>
+
| <math>((~))\!</math>
| <math>((~))</math>
+
| <math>((~))\!</math>
 
|- style="background:#f0f0ff"
 
|- style="background:#f0f0ff"
 
| colspan="2" | <math>\text{Fixed Point Total}\!</math>
 
| colspan="2" | <math>\text{Fixed Point Total}\!</math>
Line 2,650: Line 2,657:
 
<br>
 
<br>
  
The shift operator <math>\operatorname{E}</math> can be understood as enacting a ''substitution operation'' on the proposition that is given as its argument.
+
The shift operator <math>\mathrm{E}\!</math> can be understood as enacting a ''substitution operation'' on the proposition that is given as its argument.
  
For example, the action of <math>\operatorname{E}</math> on the conjunction <math>f(x, y) = xy\!</math> is defined as follows:
+
For example, the action of <math>\mathrm{E}\!</math> on the conjunction <math>f(x, y) = xy\!</math> is defined as follows:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{array}{lcl}
 
<math>\begin{array}{lcl}
\operatorname{E} ~:~ (U \to \mathbb{B})
+
\mathrm{E} ~:~ (U \to \mathbb{B})
 
& \to &
 
& \to &
(\operatorname{E}U \to \mathbb{B}),
+
(\mathrm{E}U \to \mathbb{B}),
 
\\[6pt]
 
\\[6pt]
\operatorname{E} ~:~ f(x, y)
+
\mathrm{E} ~:~ f(x, y)
 
& \mapsto &
 
& \mapsto &
\operatorname{E}f(x, y, \operatorname{d}x, \operatorname{d}y),
+
\mathrm{E}f(x, y, \mathrm{d}x, \mathrm{d}y),
 
\\[6pt]
 
\\[6pt]
\operatorname{E}f(x, y, \operatorname{d}x, \operatorname{d}y)
+
\mathrm{E}f(x, y, \mathrm{d}x, \mathrm{d}y)
 
& = &
 
& = &
f(x + \operatorname{d}x, y + \operatorname{d}y).
+
f(x + \mathrm{d}x, y + \mathrm{d}y).
\end{array}</math>
+
\end{array}\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
Evaluating <math>\operatorname{E}f</math> at particular values of <math>\operatorname{d}x</math> and <math>\operatorname{d}y,</math> for example, <math>\operatorname{d}x = i</math> and <math>\operatorname{d}y = j,</math> where <math>i\!</math> and <math>j\!</math> are values in <math>\mathbb{B},</math> produces the following result:
+
Evaluating <math>\mathrm{E}f\!</math> at particular values of <math>\mathrm{d}x\!</math> and <math>\mathrm{d}y,\!</math> for example, <math>\mathrm{d}x = i\!</math> and <math>\mathrm{d}y = j,\!</math> where <math>i\!</math> and <math>j\!</math> are values in <math>\mathbb{B},\!</math> produces the following result:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{array}{lclcl}
 
<math>\begin{array}{lclcl}
\operatorname{E}_{ij}
+
\mathrm{E}_{ij}
 
& : &
 
& : &
 
(U \to \mathbb{B})
 
(U \to \mathbb{B})
Line 2,682: Line 2,689:
 
(U \to \mathbb{B}),
 
(U \to \mathbb{B}),
 
\\[6pt]
 
\\[6pt]
\operatorname{E}_{ij}
+
\mathrm{E}_{ij}
 
& : &
 
& : &
 
f
 
f
 
& \mapsto &
 
& \mapsto &
\operatorname{E}_{ij}f,
+
\mathrm{E}_{ij}f,
 
\\[6pt]
 
\\[6pt]
\operatorname{E}_{ij}f
+
\mathrm{E}_{ij}f
 
& = &
 
& = &
\operatorname{E}f|_{\operatorname{d}x = i, \operatorname{d}y = j}
+
\mathrm{E}f|_{\mathrm{d}x = i, \mathrm{d}y = j}
 
& = &
 
& = &
 
f(x + i, y + j).
 
f(x + i, y + j).
\end{array}</math>
+
\end{array}\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
The notation is a little awkward, but the data of Table&nbsp;A3 should make the sense clear.  The important thing to observe is that <math>\operatorname{E}_{ij}</math> has the effect of transforming each proposition <math>f : U \to \mathbb{B}</math> into a proposition <math>f^\prime : U \to \mathbb{B}.</math>  As it happens, the action of each <math>\operatorname{E}_{ij}</math> is one-to-one and onto, so the gang of four operators <math>\{ \operatorname{E}_{ij} : i, j \in \mathbb{B} \}</math> is an example of what is called a ''transformation group'' on the set of sixteen propositions.  Bowing to a longstanding local and linear tradition, I will therefore redub the four elements of this group as <math>\operatorname{T}_{00}, \operatorname{T}_{01}, \operatorname{T}_{10}, \operatorname{T}_{11},</math> to bear in mind their transformative character, or nature, as the case may be.  Abstractly viewed, this group of order four has the following operation table:
+
The notation is a little awkward, but the data of Table&nbsp;A3 should make the sense clear.  The important thing to observe is that <math>\mathrm{E}_{ij}\!</math> has the effect of transforming each proposition <math>f : U \to \mathbb{B}\!</math> into a proposition <math>f^\prime : U \to \mathbb{B}.\!</math>  As it happens, the action of each <math>\mathrm{E}_{ij}\!</math> is one-to-one and onto, so the gang of four operators <math>\{ \mathrm{E}_{ij} : i, j \in \mathbb{B} \}\!</math> is an example of what is called a ''transformation group'' on the set of sixteen propositions.  Bowing to a longstanding local and linear tradition, I will therefore redub the four elements of this group as <math>\mathrm{T}_{00}, \mathrm{T}_{01}, \mathrm{T}_{10}, \mathrm{T}_{11},\!</math> to bear in mind their transformative character, or nature, as the case may be.  Abstractly viewed, this group of order four has the following operation table:
  
 
<br>
 
<br>
Line 2,702: Line 2,709:
 
{| align="center" cellpadding="0" cellspacing="0" style="border-left:1px solid black; border-top:1px solid black; border-right:1px solid black; border-bottom:1px solid black; text-align:center; width:60%"
 
{| align="center" cellpadding="0" cellspacing="0" style="border-left:1px solid black; border-top:1px solid black; border-right:1px solid black; border-bottom:1px solid black; text-align:center; width:60%"
 
|- style="height:50px"
 
|- style="height:50px"
| width="12%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black; border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\cdot</math>
+
| width="12%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black; border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\cdot\!</math>
 
| width="22%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black" |
 
| width="22%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black" |
<math>\operatorname{T}_{00}</math>
+
<math>\mathrm{T}_{00}\!</math>
 
| width="22%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black" |
 
| width="22%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black" |
<math>\operatorname{T}_{01}</math>
+
<math>\mathrm{T}_{01}\!</math>
 
| width="22%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black" |
 
| width="22%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black" |
<math>\operatorname{T}_{10}</math>
+
<math>\mathrm{T}_{10}\!</math>
 
| width="22%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black" |
 
| width="22%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black" |
<math>\operatorname{T}_{11}</math>
+
<math>\mathrm{T}_{11}\!</math>
 
|- style="height:50px"
 
|- style="height:50px"
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\operatorname{T}_{00}</math>
+
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\mathrm{T}_{00}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{T}_{00}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{T}_{00}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{T}_{01}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{T}_{01}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{T}_{10}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{T}_{10}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{T}_{11}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{T}_{11}\!</math>
 
|- style="height:50px"
 
|- style="height:50px"
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\operatorname{T}_{01}</math>
+
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\mathrm{T}_{01}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{T}_{01}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{T}_{01}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{T}_{00}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{T}_{00}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{T}_{11}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{T}_{11}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{T}_{10}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{T}_{10}\!</math>
 
|- style="height:50px"
 
|- style="height:50px"
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\operatorname{T}_{10}</math>
+
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\mathrm{T}_{10}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{T}_{10}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{T}_{10}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{T}_{11}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{T}_{11}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{T}_{00}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{T}_{00}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{T}_{01}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{T}_{01}\!</math>
 
|- style="height:50px"
 
|- style="height:50px"
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\operatorname{T}_{11}</math>
+
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\mathrm{T}_{11}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{T}_{11}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{T}_{11}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{T}_{10}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{T}_{10}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{T}_{01}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{T}_{01}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{T}_{00}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{T}_{00}\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
Line 2,741: Line 2,748:
 
It happens that there are just two possible groups of 4 elements.  One is the cyclic group <math>Z_4\!</math> (from German ''Zyklus''), which this is not.  The other is the Klein four-group <math>V_4\!</math> (from German ''Vier''), which this is.
 
It happens that there are just two possible groups of 4 elements.  One is the cyclic group <math>Z_4\!</math> (from German ''Zyklus''), which this is not.  The other is the Klein four-group <math>V_4\!</math> (from German ''Vier''), which this is.
  
More concretely viewed, the group as a whole pushes the set of sixteen propositions around in such a way that they fall into seven natural classes, called ''orbits''.  One says that the orbits are preserved by the action of the group.  There is an ''Orbit Lemma'' of immense utility to "those who count" which, depending on your upbringing, you may associate with the names of Burnside, Cauchy, Frobenius, or some subset or superset of these three, vouching that the number of orbits is equal to the mean number of fixed points, in other words, the total number of points (in our case, propositions) that are left unmoved by the separate operations, divided by the order of the group.  In this instance, <math>\operatorname{T}_{00}</math> operates as the group identity, fixing all 16 propositions, while the other three group elements fix 4 propositions each, and so we get:  <math>\text{Number of orbits}~ = (4 + 4 + 4 + 16) \div 4 = 7.</math>  Amazing!
+
More concretely viewed, the group as a whole pushes the set of sixteen propositions around in such a way that they fall into seven natural classes, called ''orbits''.  One says that the orbits are preserved by the action of the group.  There is an ''Orbit Lemma'' of immense utility to "those who count" which, depending on your upbringing, you may associate with the names of Burnside, Cauchy, Frobenius, or some subset or superset of these three, vouching that the number of orbits is equal to the mean number of fixed points, in other words, the total number of points (in our case, propositions) that are left unmoved by the separate operations, divided by the order of the group.  In this instance, <math>\mathrm{T}_{00}\!</math> operates as the group identity, fixing all 16 propositions, while the other three group elements fix 4 propositions each, and so we get:  <math>\text{Number of orbits}~ = (4 + 4 + 4 + 16) \div 4 = 7.\!</math>  Amazing!
  
 
==Note 8==
 
==Note 8==
  
We have been contemplating functions of the type <math>f : U \to \mathbb{B}</math> and studying the action of the operators <math>\operatorname{E}</math> and <math>\operatorname{D}</math> on this family.  These functions, that we may identify for our present aims with propositions, inasmuch as they capture their abstract forms, are logical analogues of ''scalar potential fields''.  These are the sorts of fields that are so picturesquely presented in elementary calculus and physics textbooks by images of snow-covered hills and parties of skiers who trek down their slopes like least action heroes.  The analogous scene in propositional logic presents us with forms more reminiscent of plateaunic idylls, being all plains at one of two levels, the mesas of verity and falsity, as it were, with nary a niche to inhabit between them, restricting our options for a sporting gradient of downhill dynamics to just one of two:  standing still on level ground or falling off a bluff.
+
We have been contemplating functions of the type <math>f : U \to \mathbb{B}\!</math> and studying the action of the operators <math>\mathrm{E}\!</math> and <math>\mathrm{D}\!</math> on this family.  These functions, that we may identify for our present aims with propositions, inasmuch as they capture their abstract forms, are logical analogues of ''scalar potential fields''.  These are the sorts of fields that are so picturesquely presented in elementary calculus and physics textbooks by images of snow-covered hills and parties of skiers who trek down their slopes like least action heroes.  The analogous scene in propositional logic presents us with forms more reminiscent of plateaunic idylls, being all plains at one of two levels, the mesas of verity and falsity, as it were, with nary a niche to inhabit between them, restricting our options for a sporting gradient of downhill dynamics to just one of two:  standing still on level ground or falling off a bluff.
  
We are still working well within the logical analogue of the classical finite difference calculus, taking in the novelties that the logical transmutation of familiar elements is able to bring to light.  Soon we will take up several different notions of approximation relationships that may be seen to organize the space of propositions, and these will allow us to define several different forms of differential analysis applying to propositions.  In time we will find reason to consider more general types of maps, having concrete types of the form <math>X_1 \times \ldots \times X_k \to Y_1 \times \ldots \times Y_n</math> and abstract types <math>\mathbb{B}^k \to \mathbb{B}^n.</math>  We will think of these mappings as transforming universes of discourse into themselves or into others, in short, as ''transformations of discourse''.
+
We are still working well within the logical analogue of the classical finite difference calculus, taking in the novelties that the logical transmutation of familiar elements is able to bring to light.  Soon we will take up several different notions of approximation relationships that may be seen to organize the space of propositions, and these will allow us to define several different forms of differential analysis applying to propositions.  In time we will find reason to consider more general types of maps, having concrete types of the form <math>X_1 \times \ldots \times X_k \to Y_1 \times \ldots \times Y_n\!</math> and abstract types <math>\mathbb{B}^k \to \mathbb{B}^n.\!</math>  We will think of these mappings as transforming universes of discourse into themselves or into others, in short, as ''transformations of discourse''.
  
 
Before we continue with this intinerary, however, I would like to highlight another sort of differential aspect that concerns the ''boundary operator'' or the ''marked connective'' that serves as one of the two basic connectives in the cactus language for ZOL.
 
Before we continue with this intinerary, however, I would like to highlight another sort of differential aspect that concerns the ''boundary operator'' or the ''marked connective'' that serves as one of the two basic connectives in the cactus language for ZOL.
  
For example, consider the proposition <math>f\!</math> of concrete type <math>f : X \times Y \times Z \to \mathbb{B}</math> and abstract type <math>f : \mathbb{B}^3 \to \mathbb{B}</math> that is written <math>\texttt{(} x, y, z \texttt{)}</math> in cactus syntax.  Taken as an assertion in what Peirce called the ''existential interpretation'', <math>\texttt{(} x, y, z \texttt{)}</math> says that just one of <math>x, y, z\!</math> is false.  It is useful to consider this assertion in relation to the conjunction <math>xyz\!</math> of the features that are engaged as its arguments.  A venn diagram of <math>\texttt{(} x, y, z \texttt{)}</math> looks like this:
+
For example, consider the proposition <math>f\!</math> of concrete type <math>f : X \times Y \times Z \to \mathbb{B}\!</math> and abstract type <math>f : \mathbb{B}^3 \to \mathbb{B}\!</math> that is written <math>\texttt{(} x, y, z \texttt{)}\!</math> in cactus syntax.  Taken as an assertion in what Peirce called the ''existential interpretation'', <math>\texttt{(} x, y, z \texttt{)}\!</math> says that just one of <math>x, y, z\!</math> is false.  It is useful to consider this assertion in relation to the conjunction <math>xyz\!</math> of the features that are engaged as its arguments.  A venn diagram of <math>\texttt{(} x, y, z \texttt{)}\!</math> looks like this:
  
 
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
 
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
Line 2,757: Line 2,764:
 
|}
 
|}
  
In relation to the center cell indicated by the conjunction <math>xyz,\!</math> the region indicated by <math>\texttt{(} x, y, z \texttt{)}</math> is comprised of the adjacent or bordering cells.  Thus they are the cells that are just across the boundary of the center cell, as if reached by way of Leibniz's ''minimal changes'' from the point of origin, here, <math>xyz.\!</math>
+
In relation to the center cell indicated by the conjunction <math>xyz,\!</math> the region indicated by <math>\texttt{(} x, y, z \texttt{)}\!</math> is comprised of the adjacent or bordering cells.  Thus they are the cells that are just across the boundary of the center cell, as if reached by way of Leibniz's ''minimal changes'' from the point of origin, here, <math>xyz.\!</math>
  
The same sort of boundary relationship holds for any cell of origin that one chooses to indicate.  One way to indicate a cell is by forming a logical conjunction of positive and negative basis features, that is, by constructing an expression of the form <math>e_1 \cdot \ldots \cdot e_k,</math> where <math>e_j = x_j ~\text{or}~ e_j = \texttt{(} x_j \texttt{)},</math> for <math>j = 1 ~\text{to}~ k.</math>  The proposition <math>\texttt{(} e_1, \ldots, e_k \texttt{)}</math> indicates the disjunctive region consisting of the cells that are just next door to <math>e_1 \cdot \ldots \cdot e_k.</math>
+
The same sort of boundary relationship holds for any cell of origin that one chooses to indicate.  One way to indicate a cell is by forming a logical conjunction of positive and negative basis features, that is, by constructing an expression of the form <math>e_1 \cdot \ldots \cdot e_k,\!</math> where <math>e_j = x_j ~\text{or}~ e_j = \texttt{(} x_j \texttt{)},\!</math> for <math>j = 1 ~\text{to}~ k.\!</math>  The proposition <math>\texttt{(} e_1, \ldots, e_k \texttt{)}\!</math> indicates the disjunctive region consisting of the cells that are just next door to <math>e_1 \cdot \ldots \cdot e_k.\!</math>
  
 
==Note 9==
 
==Note 9==
Line 2,778: Line 2,785:
 
{| align="center" cellpadding="0" cellspacing="0" style="border-left:1px solid black; border-top:1px solid black; border-right:1px solid black; border-bottom:1px solid black; text-align:center; width:60%"
 
{| align="center" cellpadding="0" cellspacing="0" style="border-left:1px solid black; border-top:1px solid black; border-right:1px solid black; border-bottom:1px solid black; text-align:center; width:60%"
 
|- style="height:50px"
 
|- style="height:50px"
| width="12%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black; border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\cdot</math>
+
| width="12%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black; border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\cdot\!</math>
 
| width="22%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black" |
 
| width="22%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black" |
<math>\operatorname{e}</math>
+
<math>\mathrm{e}\!</math>
 
| width="22%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black" |
 
| width="22%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black" |
<math>\operatorname{f}</math>
+
<math>\mathrm{f}\!</math>
 
| width="22%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black" |
 
| width="22%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black" |
<math>\operatorname{g}</math>
+
<math>\mathrm{g}\!</math>
 
| width="22%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black" |
 
| width="22%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black" |
<math>\operatorname{h}</math>
+
<math>\mathrm{h}\!</math>
 
|- style="height:50px"
 
|- style="height:50px"
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\operatorname{e}</math>
+
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\mathrm{e}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{e}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{e}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{f}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{f}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{g}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{g}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{h}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{h}\!</math>
 
|- style="height:50px"
 
|- style="height:50px"
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\operatorname{f}</math>
+
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\mathrm{f}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{f}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{f}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{e}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{e}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{h}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{h}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{g}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{g}\!</math>
 
|- style="height:50px"
 
|- style="height:50px"
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\operatorname{g}</math>
+
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\mathrm{g}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{g}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{g}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{h}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{h}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{e}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{e}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{f}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{f}\!</math>
 
|- style="height:50px"
 
|- style="height:50px"
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\operatorname{h}</math>
+
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\mathrm{h}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{h}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{h}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{g}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{g}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{f}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{f}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{e}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{e}\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
 
<br>
 
<br>
  
This operation table is abstractly the same as, or isomorphic to, the versions with the <math>\operatorname{E}_{ij}</math> operators and the <math>\operatorname{T}_{ij}</math> transformations that we discussed earlier.  That is to say, the story is the same &mdash; only the names have been changed.  An abstract group can have a multitude of significantly and superficially different representations.  Even after we have long forgotten the details of the particular representation that we may have come in with, there are species of concrete representations, called the ''regular representations'', that are always readily available, as they can be generated from the mere data of the abstract operation table itself.
+
This operation table is abstractly the same as, or isomorphic to, the versions with the <math>\mathrm{E}_{ij}\!</math> operators and the <math>\mathrm{T}_{ij}\!</math> transformations that we discussed earlier.  That is to say, the story is the same &mdash; only the names have been changed.  An abstract group can have a multitude of significantly and superficially different representations.  Even after we have long forgotten the details of the particular representation that we may have come in with, there are species of concrete representations, called the ''regular representations'', that are always readily available, as they can be generated from the mere data of the abstract operation table itself.
  
To see how a regular representation is constructed from the abstract operation table, pick a group element at the top of the table and "consider its effects" on each of the group elements listed on the left.  These effects may be recorded in one of the ways that Peirce often used, as a ''logical aggregate'' of elementary dyadic relatives, that is, as a logical disjunction or sum whose terms represent the <math>\operatorname{input} : \operatorname{output}</math> pairs that are produced by each group element in turn.  This forms one of the two possible ''regular representations'' of the group, specifically, the one that is called the ''post-regular representation'' or the ''right regular representation''.  It has long been conventional to organize the terms of this logical sum in the form of a matrix:
+
To see how a regular representation is constructed from the abstract operation table, pick a group element at the top of the table and "consider its effects" on each of the group elements listed on the left.  These effects may be recorded in one of the ways that Peirce often used, as a ''logical aggregate'' of elementary dyadic relatives, that is, as a logical disjunction or sum whose terms represent the <math>\mathrm{input} : \mathrm{output}\!</math> pairs that are produced by each group element in turn.  This forms one of the two possible ''regular representations'' of the group, specifically, the one that is called the ''post-regular representation'' or the ''right regular representation''.  It has long been conventional to organize the terms of this logical sum in the form of a matrix:
  
 
Reading "<math>+\!</math>" as a logical disjunction:
 
Reading "<math>+\!</math>" as a logical disjunction:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
| <math>\mathrm{G} ~=~ \mathrm{e} ~+~ \mathrm{f} ~+~ \mathrm{g} ~+~ \mathrm{h}</math>
+
| align="center" |
 +
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
\mathrm{G}
 +
& = & \mathrm{e}
 +
& + & \mathrm{f}
 +
& + & \mathrm{g}
 +
& + & \mathrm{h}
 +
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
 
And so, by expanding effects, we get:
 
And so, by expanding effects, we get:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
|
+
| align="center" |
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
\mathrm{G}
 
\mathrm{G}
Line 2,850: Line 2,864:
 
& + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{f}
 
& + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{f}
 
& + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{e}
 
& + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{e}
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
Line 2,861: Line 2,875:
 
The idea about the regular representations of a group is universally known as Cayley's Theorem, typically stated in the following form:
 
The idea about the regular representations of a group is universally known as Cayley's Theorem, typically stated in the following form:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
| Every group is isomorphic to a subgroup of <math>\operatorname{Aut}(S),</math> the group of automorphisms of a suitable set <math>S\!</math>.
+
| Every group is isomorphic to a subgroup of <math>\mathrm{Aut}(S),\!</math> the group of automorphisms of a suitable set <math>S\!</math>.
 
|}
 
|}
  
 
There is a considerable generalization of these regular representations to a broad class of relational algebraic systems in Peirce's earliest papers.  The crux of the whole idea is this:
 
There is a considerable generalization of these regular representations to a broad class of relational algebraic systems in Peirce's earliest papers.  The crux of the whole idea is this:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
 
| Consider the effects of the symbol, whose meaning you wish to investigate, as they play out on all the stages of context where you can imagine that symbol playing a role.
 
| Consider the effects of the symbol, whose meaning you wish to investigate, as they play out on all the stages of context where you can imagine that symbol playing a role.
 
|}
 
|}
  
This idea of contextual definition is basically the same as Jeremy Bentham's notion of ''paraphrasis'', a "method of accounting for fictions by explaining various purported terms away" (Quine, in Van Heijenoort, p.&nbsp;216).  Today we'd call these constructions ''term models''.  This, again, is the big idea behind Schönfinkel's combinators <math>\operatorname{S}, \operatorname{K}, \operatorname{I},</math> and hence of lambda calculus, and I reckon you know where that leads.
+
This idea of contextual definition is basically the same as Jeremy Bentham's notion of ''paraphrasis'', a "method of accounting for fictions by explaining various purported terms away" (Quine, in Van Heijenoort, p.&nbsp;216).  Today we'd call these constructions ''term models''.  This, again, is the big idea behind Schönfinkel's combinators <math>\mathrm{S}, \mathrm{K}, \mathrm{I},\!</math> and hence of lambda calculus, and I reckon you know where that leads.
  
 
==Note 11==
 
==Note 11==
Line 2,882: Line 2,896:
  
 
{| align="center" cellpadding="0" cellspacing="0" style="border-left:1px solid black; border-top:1px solid black; border-right:1px solid black; border-bottom:1px solid black; text-align:center; width:60%"
 
{| align="center" cellpadding="0" cellspacing="0" style="border-left:1px solid black; border-top:1px solid black; border-right:1px solid black; border-bottom:1px solid black; text-align:center; width:60%"
|+ <math>\text{Klein Four-Group}~ V_4</math>
+
|+ <math>\text{Klein Four-Group}~ V_4\!</math>
 
|- style="height:50px"
 
|- style="height:50px"
| width="12%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black; border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\cdot</math>
+
| width="12%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black; border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\cdot\!</math>
 
| width="22%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black" |
 
| width="22%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black" |
<math>\operatorname{e}</math>
+
<math>\mathrm{e}\!</math>
 
| width="22%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black" |
 
| width="22%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black" |
<math>\operatorname{f}</math>
+
<math>\mathrm{f}\!</math>
 
| width="22%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black" |
 
| width="22%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black" |
<math>\operatorname{g}</math>
+
<math>\mathrm{g}\!</math>
 
| width="22%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black" |
 
| width="22%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black" |
<math>\operatorname{h}</math>
+
<math>\mathrm{h}\!</math>
 
|- style="height:50px"
 
|- style="height:50px"
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\operatorname{e}</math>
+
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\mathrm{e}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{e}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{e}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{f}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{f}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{g}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{g}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{h}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{h}\!</math>
 
|- style="height:50px"
 
|- style="height:50px"
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\operatorname{f}</math>
+
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\mathrm{f}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{f}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{f}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{e}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{e}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{h}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{h}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{g}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{g}\!</math>
 
|- style="height:50px"
 
|- style="height:50px"
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\operatorname{g}</math>
+
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\mathrm{g}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{g}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{g}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{h}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{h}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{e}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{e}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{f}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{f}\!</math>
 
|- style="height:50px"
 
|- style="height:50px"
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\operatorname{h}</math>
+
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\mathrm{h}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{h}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{h}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{g}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{g}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{f}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{f}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{e}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{e}\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
Line 2,925: Line 2,939:
 
Reading "<math>+\!</math>" as a logical disjunction:
 
Reading "<math>+\!</math>" as a logical disjunction:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
| <math>\mathrm{G} ~=~ \mathrm{e} ~+~ \mathrm{f} ~+~ \mathrm{g} ~+~ \mathrm{h}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{G} ~=~ \mathrm{e} ~+~ \mathrm{f} ~+~ \mathrm{g} ~+~ \mathrm{h}~\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
 
Expanding effects, we get:
 
Expanding effects, we get:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 2,954: Line 2,968:
 
& + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{f}
 
& + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{f}
 
& + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{e}
 
& + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{e}
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
Line 2,963: Line 2,977:
 
Working through the construction for each one of the four group elements, we arrive at the following exegeses of their senses, giving their regular post-representations:
 
Working through the construction for each one of the four group elements, we arrive at the following exegeses of their senses, giving their regular post-representations:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 2,989: Line 3,003:
 
& + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{f}
 
& + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{f}
 
& + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{e}
 
& + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{e}
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
So if somebody asks you, say, "What is <math>\operatorname{g}</math>?", you can say, "I don't know for certain, but in practice its effects go a bit like this:
+
So if somebody asks you, say, "What is <math>\mathrm{g}\!</math>?", you can say, "I don't know for certain, but in practice its effects go a bit like this:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
| <math>\operatorname{g} \quad \text{converts} \quad \operatorname{e} ~\text{to}~ \operatorname{g}, \quad \operatorname{f} ~\text{to}~ \operatorname{h}, \quad \operatorname{g} ~\text{to}~ \operatorname{e}, \quad \operatorname{h} ~\text{to}~ \operatorname{f}.</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{g} \quad \text{converts} \quad \mathrm{e} ~\text{to}~ \mathrm{g}, \quad \mathrm{f} ~\text{to}~ \mathrm{h}, \quad \mathrm{g} ~\text{to}~ \mathrm{e}, \quad \mathrm{h} ~\text{to}~ \mathrm{f}.\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
Line 3,002: Line 3,016:
 
Working through this alternative for each one of the four group elements, we arrive at the following exegeses of their senses, giving their regular ante-representations:
 
Working through this alternative for each one of the four group elements, we arrive at the following exegeses of their senses, giving their regular ante-representations:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
Line 3,028: Line 3,042:
 
& + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{g}
 
& + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{g}
 
& + & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{h}
 
& + & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{h}
\end{matrix}</math>
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
Line 3,050: Line 3,064:
 
Peirce describes the action of an "elementary dual relative" in this way:
 
Peirce describes the action of an "elementary dual relative" in this way:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
| [Let] <math>A\!:\!B</math> be taken to denote the elementary relative which multiplied into <math>B\!</math> gives <math>A.\!</math>
+
| Elementary simple relatives are connected together in systems of four.  For if <math>\mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{B}\!</math> be taken to denote the elementary relative which multiplied into <math>\mathrm{B}\!</math> gives <math>\mathrm{A},\!</math> then this relation existing as elementary, we have the four elementary relatives
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" | <math>\mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{A} \qquad \mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{B} \qquad \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{A} \qquad \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{B}.\!</math>
 
|-
 
|-
 
| C.S. Peirce, ''Collected Papers'', CP&nbsp;3.123.
 
| C.S. Peirce, ''Collected Papers'', CP&nbsp;3.123.
Line 3,058: Line 3,074:
 
And though he is well aware that it is not at all necessary to arrange elementary relatives into arrays, matrices, or tables, when he does so he tends to prefer organizing dyadic relations in the following manner:
 
And though he is well aware that it is not at all necessary to arrange elementary relatives into arrays, matrices, or tables, when he does so he tends to prefer organizing dyadic relations in the following manner:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
|
+
| align="center" |
 
<math>\begin{bmatrix}
 
<math>\begin{bmatrix}
A:A & A:B & A:C
+
\mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{A} & \mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{B} & \mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{C}
 
\\
 
\\
B:A & B:B & B:C
+
\mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{B} & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{C}
 
\\
 
\\
C:A & C:B & C:C
+
\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{A} & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C}
\end{bmatrix}</math>
+
\end{bmatrix}\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
 
That conforms to the way that the last school of thought I matriculated into stipulated that we tabulate material:
 
That conforms to the way that the last school of thought I matriculated into stipulated that we tabulate material:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
|
+
| align="center" |
 
<math>\begin{bmatrix}
 
<math>\begin{bmatrix}
 
e_{11} & e_{12} & e_{13}
 
e_{11} & e_{12} & e_{13}
Line 3,079: Line 3,095:
 
\\
 
\\
 
e_{31} & e_{32} & e_{33}
 
e_{31} & e_{32} & e_{33}
\end{bmatrix}</math>
+
\end{bmatrix}\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
So, for example, let us suppose that we have the small universe <math>\{ A, B, C \},\!</math> and the 2-adic relation <math>m = {}^{\backprime\backprime}\, \text{mover of}\, \underline{~~~~}\, {}^{\prime\prime}</math> that is represented by this matrix:
+
So, for example, let us suppose that we have the small universe <math>\{ \mathrm{A}, \mathrm{B}, \mathrm{C} \},\!</math> and the 2-adic relation <math>\mathit{m} = {}^{\backprime\backprime}\, \text{mover of}\, \underline{[[User:Jon Awbrey|Jon Awbrey]] ([[User talk:Jon Awbrey|talk]]) 16:08, 11 December 2014 (UTC)}\, {}^{\prime\prime}\!</math> that is represented by the following matrix:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
|
+
| align="center" |
<math>
+
<math>\begin{bmatrix}
m ~=~
+
m_\mathrm{AA} (\mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{A}) &
\begin{bmatrix}
+
m_\mathrm{AB} (\mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{B}) &
m_{AA} (A:A) & m_{AB} (A:B) & m_{AC} (A:C)
+
m_\mathrm{AC} (\mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{C})
 
\\
 
\\
m_{BA} (B:A) & m_{BB} (B:B) & m_{BC} (B:C)
+
m_\mathrm{BA} (\mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{A}) &
 +
m_\mathrm{BB} (\mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{B}) &
 +
m_\mathrm{BC} (\mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{C})
 
\\
 
\\
m_{CA} (C:A) & m_{CB} (C:B) & m_{CC} (C:C)
+
m_\mathrm{CA} (\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{A}) &
\end{bmatrix}
+
m_\mathrm{CB} (\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{B}) &
</math>
+
m_\mathrm{CC} (\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C})
 +
\end{bmatrix}\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
Also, let <math>m\!</math> be such that
+
Also, let <math>\mathit{m}\!</math> be such that:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
|
+
| align="center" |
 
<math>\begin{array}{l}
 
<math>\begin{array}{l}
A ~\text{is a mover of}~ A ~\text{and}~ B,
+
\mathrm{A} ~\text{is a mover of}~ \mathrm{A} ~\text{and}~ \mathrm{B},
 
\\
 
\\
B ~\text{is a mover of}~ B ~\text{and}~ C,
+
\mathrm{B} ~\text{is a mover of}~ \mathrm{B} ~\text{and}~ \mathrm{C},
 
\\
 
\\
C ~\text{is a mover of}~ C ~\text{and}~ A.
+
\mathrm{C} ~\text{is a mover of}~ \mathrm{C} ~\text{and}~ \mathrm{A}.
\end{array}</math>
+
\end{array}\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
In sum:
+
In sum, <math>\mathit{m}\!</math> is represented by the following matrix:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
|
+
| align="center" |
<math>
+
<math>\begin{bmatrix}
m ~=~
+
1 \cdot (\mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{A}) &
\begin{bmatrix}
+
1 \cdot (\mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{B}) &
1 \cdot (A:A) & 1 \cdot (A:B) & 0 \cdot (A:C)
+
0 \cdot (\mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{C})
 
\\
 
\\
0 \cdot (B:A) & 1 \cdot (B:B) & 1 \cdot (B:C)
+
0 \cdot (\mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{A}) &
 +
1 \cdot (\mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{B}) &
 +
1 \cdot (\mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{C})
 
\\
 
\\
1 \cdot (C:A) & 0 \cdot (C:B) & 1 \cdot (C:C)
+
1 \cdot (\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{A}) &
\end{bmatrix}
+
0 \cdot (\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{B}) &
</math>
+
1 \cdot (\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C})
 +
\end{bmatrix}\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
Line 3,137: Line 3,159:
 
In the paper "On the Relative Forms of Quaternions" (CP 3.323), we observe Peirce providing the following sorts of explanation:
 
In the paper "On the Relative Forms of Quaternions" (CP 3.323), we observe Peirce providing the following sorts of explanation:
  
<pre>
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
| If X, Y, Z denote the three rectangular components of a vector, and W denote
 
| numerical unity (or a fourth rectangular component, involving space of four
 
| dimensions), and (Y:Z) denote the operation of converting the Y component
 
| of a vector into its Z component, then
 
 
|
 
|
|     1 = (W:W) + (X:X) + (Y:Y) + (Z:Z)
+
<p>If <math>X, Y, Z\!</math> denote the three rectangular components of a vector, and <math>W\!</math> denote numerical unity (or a fourth rectangular component, involving space of four dimensions), and <math>(Y:Z)\!</math> denote the operation of converting the <math>Y\!</math> component of a vector into its <math>Z\!</math> component, then</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" |
 +
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
1 & = & (W:W) & + & (X:X) & + & (Y:Y) & + & (Z:Z)
 +
\\
 +
i & = & (X:W) & - & (W:X) & - & (Y:Z) & + & (Z:Y)
 +
\\
 +
j & = & (Y:W) & - & (W:Y) & - & (Z:X) & + & (X:Z)
 +
\\
 +
k & = & (Z:W) & - & (W:Z) & - & (X:Y) & + & (Y:X)
 +
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 +
|-
 
|
 
|
|    i  = (X:W) - (W:X) - (Y:Z) + (Z:Y)
+
<p>In the language of logic <math>(Y:Z)\!</math> is a relative term whose relate is a <math>Y\!</math> component, and whose correlate is a <math>Z\!</math> component. The law of multiplication is plainly <math>(Y:Z)(Z:X) = (Y:X),\!</math> <math>(Y:Z)(X:W) = 0,\!</math> and the application of these rules to the above values of <math>1, i, j, k\!</math> gives the quaternion relations</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" |
 +
<math>i^2 = j^2 = k^2 = -1, \quad ijk = -1, \quad \text{etc}.\!</math>
 +
|-
 
|
 
|
|    j  =  (Y:W) - (W:Y) - (Z:X) + (X:Z)
+
<p>The symbol <math>a(Y:Z)\!</math> denotes the changing of <math>Y\!</math> to <math>Z\!</math> and the multiplication of the result by <math>a.\!</math>  If the relatives be arranged in a block</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" |
 +
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
W:W && W:X && W:Y && W:Z
 +
\\
 +
X:W && X:X && X:Y && X:Z
 +
\\
 +
Y:W && Y:X && Y:Y && Y:Z
 +
\\
 +
Z:W && Z:X && Z:Y && Z:Z
 +
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 +
|-
 
|
 
|
|     k = (Z:W) - (W:Z) - (X:Y) + (Y:X)
+
<p>then the quaternion <math>w + xi + yj + zk\!</math> is represented by the matrix of numbers</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="center" |
 +
<math>\begin{array}{*{7}{r}}
 +
w && -x && -y && -z
 +
\\
 +
x && w && -z &&  y
 +
\\
 +
y &&  z && w && -x
 +
\\
 +
z && -y &&  x &&  w
 +
\end{array}\!</math>
 +
|-
 
|
 
|
| In the language of logic (Y:Z) is a relative term whose relate is
+
<p>The multiplication of such matrices follows the same laws as the multiplication of quaternions.  The determinant of the matrix = the fourth power of the tensor of the quaternion.</p>
| a Y component, and whose correlate is a Z component.  The law of
+
 
| multiplication is plainly (Y:Z)(Z:X) = (Y:X), (Y:Z)(X:W) = 0,
+
<p>The imaginary <math>x + y \sqrt{-1}\!</math> may likewise be represented by the matrix</p>
| and the application of these rules to the above values of
+
|-
| 1, i, j, k gives the quaternion relations
+
| align="center" |
 +
<math>\begin{array}{rr}
 +
x & y
 +
\\
 +
-y & x
 +
\end{array}\!</math>
 +
|-
 
|
 
|
|    i^2  =  j^2  =  k^2  =  -1,
+
<p>and the determinant of the matrix = the square of the modulus.</p>
|
+
 
|    ijk  =  -1,
+
<p>C.S. Peirce (1882), "On the Relative Forms of Quaternions", ''Johns Hopkins University Circulars'', No.&nbsp;13, p.&nbsp;179.  Reprinted, ''Collected Papers'', CP&nbsp;3.323.</p>
|
+
|}
|    etc.
 
|
 
| The symbol a(Y:Z) denotes the changing of Y to Z and the
 
| multiplication of the result by 'a'.  If the relatives be
 
| arranged in a block
 
|
 
|    W:W    W:X    W:Y    W:Z
 
|
 
|    X:W    X:X    X:Y    X:Z
 
|
 
|    Y:W    Y:X    Y:Y    Y:Z
 
|
 
|    Z:W    Z:X    Z:Y    Z:Z
 
|
 
| then the quaternion w + xi + yj + zk
 
| is represented by the matrix of numbers
 
|
 
|    w      -x      -y      -z
 
|
 
|    x        w      -z      y
 
|
 
|    y        z      w      -x
 
|
 
|    z      -y      x      w
 
|
 
| The multiplication of such matrices follows the same laws as the
 
| multiplication of quaternions.  The determinant of the matrix =
 
| the fourth power of the tensor of the quaternion.
 
|
 
| The imaginary x + y(-1)^(1/2) may likewise be represented by the matrix
 
|
 
|      x      y
 
|
 
|    -y      x
 
|
 
| and the determinant of the matrix = the square of the modulus.
 
|
 
| Charles Sanders Peirce, 'Collected Papers', CP 3.323.
 
|'Johns Hopkins University Circulars', No. 13, p. 179, 1882.
 
</pre>
 
  
 
This way of talking is the mark of a person who opts to multiply his matrices "on the rignt", as they say.  Yet Peirce still continues to call the first element of the ordered pair <math>(I:J)\!</math> its "relate" while calling the second element of the pair <math>(I:J)\!</math> its "correlate".  That doesn't comport very well, so far as I can tell, with his customary reading of relative terms, suited more to the multiplication of matrices "on the left".
 
This way of talking is the mark of a person who opts to multiply his matrices "on the rignt", as they say.  Yet Peirce still continues to call the first element of the ordered pair <math>(I:J)\!</math> its "relate" while calling the second element of the pair <math>(I:J)\!</math> its "correlate".  That doesn't comport very well, so far as I can tell, with his customary reading of relative terms, suited more to the multiplication of matrices "on the left".
Line 3,208: Line 3,232:
 
==Note 15==
 
==Note 15==
  
I have been planning for quite some time now to make my return to Peirce's "Description of a Notation for the Logic of Relatives" (1870), and I can see that it's just about time to get down to it, so let this current bit of rambling inquiry function as the preamble to that.  All we need at the present, though, is a way of telling what is substantial from what is inessential in the brook between symbolic conceits and dramatic actions that we find afforded by means of the pragmatic maxim.
+
I've been planning to return to Peirce's "Description of a Notation for the Logic of Relatives" (1870) and I can see that it's just about time to get down to it, so let this bit of rambling inquiry function as the preamble to that.  All we need at the present, though, is a way of telling what is substantial from what is inessential in the brook between symbolic conceits and dramatic actions that we find afforded by means of the pragmatic maxim.
  
Back to our "subinstance", the example in support of our first example.  I will try to reconstruct it in a less confusing way.
+
Back to our current subinstance, the example in support of our first example.  I will try to reconstruct it in a less confusing way.
  
<pre>
+
Consider the universe of discourse <math>\mathbf{1} = \mathrm{A} + \mathrm{B} + \mathrm{C}\!</math> and the 2-adic relation <math>\mathit{n} = {}^{\backprime\backprime}\, \text{noder of}\, \underline{[[User:Jon Awbrey|Jon Awbrey]] ([[User talk:Jon Awbrey|talk]]) 16:08, 11 December 2014 (UTC)}\, {}^{\prime\prime},\!</math> as when "<math>X\!</math> is a data record that contains a pointer to <math>Y\!</math>". That interpretation is not important, it's just for the sake of intuition. In general terms, the 2-adic relation <math>n\!</math> can be represented by this matrix:
Let us make up the model universe $1$ = A + B + C and the 2-adic relation
 
n = "noder of", as when "X is a data record that contains a pointer to Y".
 
That interpretation is not important, it's just for the sake of intuition.
 
In general terms, the 2-adic relation n can be represented by this matrix:
 
  
n =
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
 +
| align="center" |
 +
<math>\begin{bmatrix}
 +
\mathit{n}_\mathrm{AA} (\mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{A}) &
 +
\mathit{n}_\mathrm{AB} (\mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{B}) &
 +
\mathit{n}_\mathrm{AC} (\mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{C})
 +
\\
 +
\mathit{n}_\mathrm{BA} (\mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{A}) &
 +
\mathit{n}_\mathrm{BB} (\mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{B}) &
 +
\mathit{n}_\mathrm{BC} (\mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{C})
 +
\\
 +
\mathit{n}_\mathrm{CA} (\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{A}) &
 +
\mathit{n}_\mathrm{CB} (\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{B}) &
 +
\mathit{n}_\mathrm{CC} (\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C})
 +
\end{bmatrix}\!</math>
 +
|}
  
|  n_AA (A:A)  n_AB (A:B)  n_AC (A:C)  |
+
More specifically, let <math>\mathit{n}\!</math> be such that:
|                                        |
 
|  n_BA (B:A)  n_BB (B:B)  n_BC (B:C)  |
 
|                                        |
 
|  n_CA (C:A)  n_CB (C:B)  n_CC (C:C)  |
 
  
Also, let n be such that
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
A is a noder of A and B,
+
| align="center" |
B is a noder of B and C,
+
<math>\begin{array}{l}
C is a noder of C and A.
+
\mathrm{A} ~\text{is a noder of}~ \mathrm{A} ~\text{and}~ \mathrm{B},
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{B} ~\text{is a noder of}~ \mathrm{B} ~\text{and}~ \mathrm{C},
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{C} ~\text{is a noder of}~ \mathrm{C} ~\text{and}~ \mathrm{A}.
 +
\end{array}\!</math>
 +
|}
  
Filling in the instantial values of the "coefficients" n_ij,
+
Filling in the instantial values of the coefficients <math>\mathit{n}_{ij},\!</math> as the indices <math>i\!</math> and <math>j\!</math> range over the universe of discourse, the relation <math>\mathit{n}\!</math> is represented by the following matrix:
as the indices i and j range over the universe of discourse:
 
  
=
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
 +
| align="center" |
 +
<math>\begin{bmatrix}
 +
1 \cdot (\mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{A}) &
 +
1 \cdot (\mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{B}) &
 +
0 \cdot (\mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{C})
 +
\\
 +
0 \cdot (\mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{A}) &
 +
1 \cdot (\mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{B}) &
 +
1 \cdot (\mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{C})
 +
\\
 +
1 \cdot (\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{A}) &
 +
0 \cdot (\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{B}) &
 +
1 \cdot (\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C})
 +
\end{bmatrix}\!</math>
 +
|}
  
|  1 · (A:A)  1 · (A:B)  0 · (A:C)  |
+
In Peirce's time, and even in some circles of mathematics today, the information indicated by the elementary relatives <math>(I\!:\!J),\!</math> as <math>I, J\!</math> range over the universe of discourse, would be referred to as the ''umbral elements'' of the algebraic operation represented by the matrix, though I seem to recall that Peirce preferred to call these terms the "ingredients". When this ordered basis is understood well enough, one will tend to drop any mention of it from the matrix itself, leaving us nothing but these bare bones:
|                                    |
 
|  0 · (B:A)  1 · (B:B)  1 · (B:C|
 
|                                    |
 
|  1 · (C:A)  0 · (C:B)  1 · (C:C)  |
 
  
In Peirce's time, and even in some circles of mathematics today,
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
the information indicated by the elementary relatives (I:J), as
+
| align="center" |
I, J range over the universe of discourse, would be referred to
+
<math>\begin{bmatrix}
as the "umbral elements" of the algebraic operation represented
+
1 & 1 & 0
by the matrix, though I seem to recall that Peirce preferred to
+
\\
call these terms the "ingredients".  When this ordered basis is
+
0 & 1 & 1
understood well enough, one will tend to drop any mention of it
+
\\
from the matrix itself, leaving us nothing but these bare bones:
+
1 & 0 & 1
 
+
\end{bmatrix}\!</math>
n  =
+
|}
  
|  1  1  0  |
+
The various representations of <math>n\!</math> are nothing more than alternative ways of specifying its basic ingredients, namely, the following logical sum of elementary relatives:
|          |
 
|  0  1  1  |
 
|          |
 
|  1  0  1  |
 
  
However the specification may come to be written, this
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
is all just convenient schematics for stipulating that:
+
| align="center" |
 +
<math>\begin{array}{*{13}{c}}
 +
\mathit{n}
 +
& = & \mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{A}
 +
& + & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{B}
 +
& + & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C}
 +
& + & \mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{B}
 +
& + & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{C}
 +
& + & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{A}
 +
\end{array}\!</math>
 +
|}
  
= A:A + B:B + C:C + A:B + B:C + C:A
+
Recognizing <math>\mathit{1} = \mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{A} + \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{B} + \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C}\!</math> to be the identity transformation, the 2-adic relation <math>\mathit{n} = {}^{\backprime\backprime}\, \text{noder of}\, \underline{[[User:Jon Awbrey|Jon Awbrey]] ([[User talk:Jon Awbrey|talk]]) 16:08, 11 December 2014 (UTC)}\, {}^{\prime\prime}\!</math> may be represented by an element <math>\mathit{1} + \mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{B} + \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{C} + \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{A}\!</math> of the so-called ''group ring'', all of which just makes this element a special sort of linear transformation.
  
Recognizing !1! = A:A + B:B + C:C to be the identity transformation,
+
Up to this point, we're still reading the elementary relatives of the form <math>I:J\!</math> in the way that Peirce reads them in logical contexts: <math>I\!</math> is the relate, <math>J\!</math> is the correlate, and in our current example we read <math>I:J,\!</math> or more exactly, <math>\mathit{n}_{ij} = 1,\!</math> to say that <math>I\!</math> is a noder of <math>J.\!</math>  This is the mode of reading that we call ''multiplying on the left''.
the 2-adic relation n = "noder of" may be represented by an element
 
!1! + A:B + B:C + C:A of the so-called "group ring", all of which
 
just makes this element a special sort of linear transformation.
 
  
Up to this point, we are still reading the elementary relatives of
+
In the algebraic, permutational, or transformational contexts of application, however, Peirce converts to the alternative mode of reading, although still calling <math>I\!</math> the relate and <math>J\!</math> the correlate, the elementary relative <math>I:J\!</math> now means that <math>I\!</math> gets changed into <math>J.\!</math>  In this scheme of reading, the transformation <math>\mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{B} + \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{C} + \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{A}\!</math> is a permutation of the aggregate <math>\mathbf{1} = \mathrm{A} + \mathrm{B} + \mathrm{C},\!</math> or what we would now call the set <math>\{ \mathrm{A}, \mathrm{B}, \mathrm{C} \},\!</math> in particular, it is the permutation that is otherwise notated as follows:
the form I:J in the way that Peirce reads them in logical contexts:
 
I is the relate, J is the correlate, and in our current example we
 
read I:J, or more exactly, n_ij = 1, to say that I is a noder of J.
 
This is the mode of reading that we call "multiplying on the left".
 
  
In the algebraic, permutational, or transformational contexts of
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="6"
application, however, Peirce converts to the alternative mode of
+
|
reading, although still calling I the relate and J the correlate,
+
<math>\begin{Bmatrix}
the elementary relative I:J now means that I gets changed into J.
+
\mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C}
In this scheme of reading, the transformation A:B + B:C + C:A is
+
\\
a permutation of the aggregate $1$ = A + B + C, or what we would
+
\mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C} & \mathrm{A}
now call the set {A, B, C}, in particular, it is the permutation
+
\end{Bmatrix}\!</math>
that is otherwise notated as:
+
|}
  
( A B C )
+
This is consistent with the convention that Peirce uses in the paper "On a Class of Multiple Algebras" (CP 3.324&ndash;327).
<      >
 
( B C A )
 
 
 
This is consistent with the convention that Peirce uses in
 
the paper "On a Class of Multiple Algebras" (CP 3.324-327).
 
</pre>
 
  
 
==Note 16==
 
==Note 16==
Line 3,337: Line 3,377:
  
 
{| align="center" cellpadding="0" cellspacing="0" style="border-left:1px solid black; border-top:1px solid black; border-right:1px solid black; border-bottom:1px solid black; text-align:center; width:60%"
 
{| align="center" cellpadding="0" cellspacing="0" style="border-left:1px solid black; border-top:1px solid black; border-right:1px solid black; border-bottom:1px solid black; text-align:center; width:60%"
|+ <math>\text{Klein Four-Group}~ V_4</math>
+
|+ <math>\text{Klein Four-Group}~ V_4\!</math>
 
|- style="height:50px"
 
|- style="height:50px"
| width="12%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black; border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\cdot</math>
+
| width="12%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black; border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\cdot\!</math>
 
| width="22%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black" |
 
| width="22%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black" |
<math>\operatorname{e}</math>
+
<math>\mathrm{e}\!</math>
 
| width="22%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black" |
 
| width="22%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black" |
<math>\operatorname{f}</math>
+
<math>\mathrm{f}\!</math>
 
| width="22%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black" |
 
| width="22%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black" |
<math>\operatorname{g}</math>
+
<math>\mathrm{g}\!</math>
 
| width="22%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black" |
 
| width="22%" style="border-bottom:1px solid black" |
<math>\operatorname{h}</math>
+
<math>\mathrm{h}\!</math>
 
|- style="height:50px"
 
|- style="height:50px"
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\operatorname{e}</math>
+
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\mathrm{e}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{e}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{e}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{f}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{f}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{g}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{g}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{h}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{h}\!</math>
 
|- style="height:50px"
 
|- style="height:50px"
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\operatorname{f}</math>
+
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\mathrm{f}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{f}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{f}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{e}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{e}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{h}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{h}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{g}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{g}\!</math>
 
|- style="height:50px"
 
|- style="height:50px"
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\operatorname{g}</math>
+
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\mathrm{g}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{g}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{g}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{h}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{h}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{e}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{e}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{f}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{f}\!</math>
 
|- style="height:50px"
 
|- style="height:50px"
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\operatorname{h}</math>
+
| style="border-right:1px solid black" | <math>\mathrm{h}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{h}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{h}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{g}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{g}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{f}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{f}\!</math>
| <math>\operatorname{e}</math>
+
| <math>\mathrm{e}\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
 
<br>
 
<br>
  
A group operation table is really just a device for recording a certain 3-adic relation, to be specific, the set of triples of the form <math>(x, y, z)\!</math> satisfying the equation <math>x \cdot y = z.</math>
+
A group operation table is really just a device for recording a certain 3-adic relation, to be specific, the set of triples of the form <math>(x, y, z)\!</math> satisfying the equation <math>x \cdot y = z.\!</math>
  
In the case of <math>V_4 = (G, \cdot),</math> where <math>G\!</math> is the ''underlying set'' <math>\{ \operatorname{e}, \operatorname{f}, \operatorname{g}, \operatorname{h} \},</math> we have the 3-adic relation <math>L(V_4) \subseteq G \times G \times G</math> whose triples are listed below:
+
In the case of <math>V_4 = (G, \cdot),\!</math> where <math>G\!</math> is the ''underlying set'' <math>\{ \mathrm{e}, \mathrm{f}, \mathrm{g}, \mathrm{h} \},\!</math> we have the 3-adic relation <math>L(V_4) \subseteq G \times G \times G\!</math> whose triples are listed below:
  
<pre>
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
|  <e, e, e>
+
| align="center" |
|  <e, f, f>
+
<math>\begin{matrix}
|  <e, g, g>
+
(\mathrm{e}, \mathrm{e}, \mathrm{e}) &
|  <e, h, h>
+
(\mathrm{e}, \mathrm{f}, \mathrm{f}) &
|
+
(\mathrm{e}, \mathrm{g}, \mathrm{g}) &
|  <f, e, f>
+
(\mathrm{e}, \mathrm{h}, \mathrm{h})
|  <f, f, e>
+
\\[6pt]
|  <f, g, h>
+
(\mathrm{f}, \mathrm{e}, \mathrm{f}) &
|  <f, h, g>
+
(\mathrm{f}, \mathrm{f}, \mathrm{e}) &
|
+
(\mathrm{f}, \mathrm{g}, \mathrm{h}) &
|  <g, e, g>
+
(\mathrm{f}, \mathrm{h}, \mathrm{g})
|  <g, f, h>
+
\\[6pt]
|  <g, g, e>
+
(\mathrm{g}, \mathrm{e}, \mathrm{g}) &
|  <g, h, f>
+
(\mathrm{g}, \mathrm{f}, \mathrm{h}) &
|
+
(\mathrm{g}, \mathrm{g}, \mathrm{e}) &
|  <h, e, h>
+
(\mathrm{g}, \mathrm{h}, \mathrm{f})
|  <h, f, g>
+
\\[6pt]
|  <h, g, f>
+
(\mathrm{h}, \mathrm{e}, \mathrm{h}) &
|  <h, h, e>
+
(\mathrm{h}, \mathrm{f}, \mathrm{g}) &
 +
(\mathrm{h}, \mathrm{g}, \mathrm{f}) &
 +
(\mathrm{h}, \mathrm{h}, \mathrm{e})
 +
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 +
|}
  
It is part of the definition of a group that the 3-adic
+
It is part of the definition of a group that the 3-adic relation <math>L \subseteq G^3\!</math> is actually a function <math>L : G \times G \to G.\!</math>  It is from this functional perspective that we can see an easy way to derive the two regular representations. Since we have a function of the type <math>L : G \times G \to G,\!</math> we can define a couple of substitution operators:
relation L c G^3 is actually a function L : G x G -> G.
 
It is from this functional perspective that we can see
 
an easy way to derive the two regular representations.
 
Since we have a function of the type L : G x G -> G,
 
we can define a couple of substitution operators:
 
  
1. Sub(x, <_, y>) puts any specified x into
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
    the empty slot of the rheme <_, y>, with
+
| valign="top" | 1.
    the effect of producing the saturated
+
| <math>\mathrm{Sub}(x, (\underline{~~}, y))\!</math> puts any specified <math>x\!</math> into the empty slot of the rheme <math>(\underline{~~}, y),\!</math> with the effect of producing the saturated rheme <math>(x, y)\!</math> that evaluates to <math>x \cdot y.\!</math>
    rheme <x, y> that evaluates to x·y.
+
|-
 +
| valign="top" | 2.
 +
| <math>\mathrm{Sub}(x, (y, \underline{~~}))\!</math> puts any specified <math>x\!</math> into the empty slot of the rheme <math>(y, \underline{~~}),\!</math> with the effect of producing the saturated rheme <math>(y, x)\!</math> that evaluates to <math>y \cdot x.\!</math>
 +
|}
  
2.  Sub(x, <y, _>) puts any specified x into
+
In (1) we consider the effects of each <math>x\!</math> in its practical bearing on contexts of the form <math>(\underline{~~}, y),\!</math> as <math>y\!</math> ranges over <math>G,\!</math> and the effects are such that <math>x\!</math> takes <math>(\underline{~~}, y)\!</math> into <math>x \cdot y,\!</math> for <math>y\!</math> in <math>G,\!</math> all of which is notated as <math>x = \{ (y : x \cdot y) ~|~ y \in G \}.\!</math>  The pairs <math>(y : x \cdot y)\!</math> can be found by picking an <math>x\!</math> from the left margin of the group operation table and considering its effects on each <math>y\!</math> in turn as these run across the top margin. This aspect of pragmatic definition we recognize as the regular ante-representation:
    the empty slot of the rheme <y, >, with
 
    the effect of producing the saturated
 
    rheme <y, x> that evaluates to y·x.
 
  
In (1), we consider the effects of each x in its
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
practical bearing on contexts of the form <_, y>,
+
| align="center" |
as y ranges over G, and the effects are such that
+
<math>\begin{matrix}
x takes <_, y> into x·y, for y in G, all of which
+
\mathrm{e}
is summarily notated as x = {(y : x·y) : y in G}.
+
& = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{e}
The pairs (y : x·y) can be found by picking an x
+
& + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{f}
from the left margin of the group operation table
+
& + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{g}
and considering its effects on each y in turn as
+
& + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{h}
these run across the top margin.  This aspect of
+
\\[4pt]
pragmatic definition we recognize as the regular
+
\mathrm{f}
ante-representation:
+
& = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{f}
 
+
& + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{e}
    e  = e:e + f:f + g:g + h:h
+
& + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{h}
 
+
& + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{g}
    f = e:f + f:e + g:h +  h:g
+
\\[4pt]
 
+
\mathrm{g}
    g  =  e:g  + f:h +  g:e  +  h:f
+
& = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{g}
 
+
& + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{h}
    h  =  e:h  +  f:g +  g:f  +  h:e
+
& + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{e}
 
+
& + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{f}
In (2), we consider the effects of each x in its
+
\\[4pt]
practical bearing on contexts of the form <y, _>,
+
\mathrm{h}
as y ranges over G, and the effects are such that
+
& = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{h}
x takes <y, _> into y·x, for y in G, all of which
+
& + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{g}
is summarily notated as x = {(y : y·x) : y in G}.
+
& + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{f}
The pairs (y : y·x) can be found by picking an x
+
& + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{e}
from the top margin of the group operation table
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
and considering its effects on each y in turn as
 
these run down the left margin.  This aspect of
 
pragmatic definition we recognize as the regular
 
post-representation:
 
 
 
    e  = e:e  +  f:f  +  g:g  +  h:h
 
 
 
    f  =  e:f  + f:e  +  g:h +  h:g
 
 
 
    g  =  e:g  + f:h  +  g:e + h:f
 
 
 
    h =  e:h  +  f:g  +  g:f  +  h:e
 
 
 
If the ante-rep looks the same as the post-rep,
 
now that I'm writing them in the same dialect,
 
that is because V_4 is abelian (commutative),
 
and so the two representations have the very
 
same effects on each point of their bearing.
 
</pre>
 
 
 
==Note 19==
 
 
 
So long as we're in the neighborhood, we might as well take in some more of the sights, for instance, the smallest example of a non-abelian (non-commutative) group.  This is a group of six elements, say, <math>G = \{ \operatorname{e}, \operatorname{f}, \operatorname{g}, \operatorname{h}, \operatorname{i}, \operatorname{j} \},\!</math> with no relation to any other employment of these six symbols being implied, of course, and it can be most easily represented as the permutation group on a set of three letters, say, <math>X = \{ A, B, C \},\!</math> usually notated as <math>G = \operatorname{Sym}(X)</math> or more abstractly and briefly, as <math>\operatorname{Sym}(3)</math> or <math>S_3.\!</math>  The next Table shows the intended correspondence between abstract group elements and the permutation or substitution operations in <math>\operatorname{Sym}(X).</math>
 
 
 
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
 
| align="center" |
 
<pre>
 
Table 2.  Permutations or Substitutions in Sym_{A, B, C}
 
o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o
 
|        |        |        |        |        |        |
 
|    e    |    f    |    g    |    h    |    i    |    j    |
 
|        |        |        |        |        |        |
 
o=========o=========o=========o=========o=========o=========o
 
|        |        |        |        |        |        |
 
|  A B C  |  A B C  |  A B C  |  A B C  |  A B C  |  A B C  |
 
|        |        |        |        |        |        |
 
|  | | |  |  | | |  |  | | |  |  | | |  |  | | |  |  | | |  |
 
|  v v v  |  v v v  |  v v v  |  v v v  |  v v v  |  v v v  |
 
|        |        |        |        |        |        |
 
|  A B C  |  C A B  |  B C A  |  A C B  |  C B A  |  B A C  |
 
|        |        |        |        |        |        |
 
o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o
 
</pre>
 
 
|}
 
|}
  
Here is the operation table for <math>S_3,\!</math> given in abstract fashion:
+
In (2) we consider the effects of each <math>x\!</math> in its practical bearing on contexts of the form <math>(y, \underline{~~}),\!</math> as <math>y\!</math> ranges over <math>G,\!</math> and the effects are such that <math>x\!</math> takes <math>(y, \underline{~~})\!</math> into <math>y \cdot x,\!</math> for <math>y\!</math> in <math>G,\!</math> all of which is notated as <math>x = \{ (y : y \cdot x) ~|~ y \in G \}.\!</math>  The pairs <math>(y : y \cdot x)~\!</math> can be found by picking an <math>x\!</math> from the top margin of the group operation table and considering its effects on each <math>y\!</math> in turn as these run down the left margin.  This aspect of pragmatic definition we recognize as the regular post-representation:
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
 
| align="center" |
 
| align="center" |
<pre>
+
<math>\begin{matrix}
Table 1.  Symmetric Group S_3
+
\mathrm{e}
o-------------------------------------------------o
+
& = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{e}
|                                                |
+
& + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{f}
|                        ^                        |
+
& + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{g}
|                    e / \ e                     |
+
& + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{h}
|                      /  \                     |
+
\\[4pt]
|                    /  e \                     |
+
\mathrm{f}
|                  f / \  / \ f                 |
+
& = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{f}
|                  /  \ /  \                  |
+
& + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{e}
|                  /  f  \ f \                  |
+
& + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{h}
|              g / \   / \  / \ g              |
+
& + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{g}
|                /  \ /  \ /  \                |
+
\\[4pt]
|              /  g \ g \  g  \              |
+
\mathrm{g}
|            h / \  / \  / \  / \ h           |
+
& = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{g}
|            /  \ /  \ /  \ /  \            |
+
& + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{h}
|            /  h  \  e  \  e  \  h \            |
+
& + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{e}
|        i / \  / \  / \   / \   / \ i        |
+
& + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{f}
|          /  \ /  \ /  \ /  \ /  \          |
+
\\[4pt]
|        /  i  \ \ f \  j  \  i  \        |
+
\mathrm{h}
|      j / \   / \   / \  / \  / \  / \ j      |
+
& = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{h}
|      /  \ \ /  \ /  \ /  \ /  \      |
+
& + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{g}
|      (  j  \  j  \ j  \  i  \  h \ j  )      |
+
& + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{f}
|      \  / \  / \  / \  / \   / \   /      |
+
& + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{e}
|        \ /  \ /  \ /  \ /  \ /  \ /        |
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
|        \  h  \  h  \ e \ j  \  i  /        |
 
|          \   / \   / \  / \  / \  /          |
 
|          \ \ /  \ /  \ /  \ /          |
 
|            \ i  \  g  \ f \  h  /            |
 
|            \   / \   / \   / \  /            |
 
|              \ \ /  \ /  \ /              |
 
|              \ f \  e  \ g /              |
 
|                \  / \  / \  /                |
 
|                \ /  \ /  \ /                |
 
|                  \ g \ f /                  |
 
|                  \   / \  /                  |
 
|                    \ /  \ /                    |
 
|                    \  e /                    |
 
|                      \   /                      |
 
|                      \ /                      |
 
|                        v                        |
 
|                                                |
 
o-------------------------------------------------o
 
</pre>
 
 
|}
 
|}
  
By the way, we will meet with the symmetric group <math>S_3\!</math> again when we return to take up the study of Peirce's early paper "On a Class of Multiple Algebras" (CP 3.324&ndash;327), and also his late unpublished work "The Simplest Mathematics" (1902) (CP 4.227&ndash;323), with particular reference to the section that treats of "Trichotomic Mathematics" (CP 4.307&ndash;323).
+
If the ante-rep looks the same as the post-rep, now that I'm writing them in the same dialect, that is because <math>V_4\!</math> is abelian (commutative), and so the two representations have the very same effects on each point of their bearing.
  
==Note 20==
+
==Note 19==
  
By way of collecting a short-term pay-off for all the work &mdash; not to mention all the peirce-spiration &mdash; that we sweated out over the regular representations of the Klein 4-group <math>V_4,\!</math> let us write out as quickly as possible in ''relative form'' a minimal budget of representations of the symmetric group on three letters, <math>S_3 = \operatorname{Sym}(3).</math>  After doing the usual bit of compare and contrast among these divers representations, we will have enough concrete material beneath our abstract belts to tackle a few of the presently obscur'd details of Peirce's early "Algebra + Logic" papers.
+
So long as we're in the neighborhood, we might as well take in some more of the sights, for instance, the smallest example of a non-abelian (non-commutative) group.  This is a group of six elements, say, <math>G = \{ \mathrm{e}, \mathrm{f}, \mathrm{g}, \mathrm{h}, \mathrm{i}, \mathrm{j} \},\!</math> with no relation to any other employment of these six symbols being implied, of course, and it can be most easily represented as the permutation group on a set of three letters, say, <math>X = \{ A, B, C \},\!</math> usually notated as <math>G = \mathrm{Sym}(X)\!</math> or more abstractly and briefly, as <math>\mathrm{Sym}(3)\!</math> or <math>S_3.\!</math>  The next Table shows the intended correspondence between abstract group elements and the permutation or substitution operations in <math>\mathrm{Sym}(X).\!</math>
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
<br>
| align="center" |
 
<pre>
 
Table 1.  Permutations or Substitutions in Sym {A, B, C}
 
o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o
 
|        |        |        |        |        |        |
 
|    e    |    f    |    g    |    h    |    i    |    j    |
 
|        |        |        |        |        |        |
 
o=========o=========o=========o=========o=========o=========o
 
|        |        |        |        |        |        |
 
|  A B C  |  A B C  |  A B C  |  A B C  |  A B C  |  A B C  |
 
|        |        |        |        |        |        |
 
|  | | |  |  | | |  |  | | |  |  | | |  |  | | |  |  | | |  |
 
|  v v v  |  v v v  |  v v v  |  v v v  |  v v v  |  v v v  |
 
|        |        |        |        |        |        |
 
|  A B C  |  C A B  |  B C A  |  A C B  |  C B A  |  B A C  |
 
|        |        |        |        |        |        |
 
o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o
 
</pre>
 
|}
 
  
Writing this table in relative form generates the following natural representation of <math>S_3.\!</math>
+
{| align="center" border="1" cellpadding="8" cellspacing="0" style="background:#f8f8ff; text-align:center; width:90%"
 
+
|+ <math>\text{Permutation Substitutions in}~ \mathrm{Sym} \{ \mathrm{A}, \mathrm{B}, \mathrm{C} \}\!</math>
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
|- style="background:#f0f0ff"
 +
| width="16%" | <math>\mathrm{e}\!</math>
 +
| width="16%" | <math>\mathrm{f}\!</math>
 +
| width="16%" | <math>\mathrm{g}\!</math>
 +
| width="16%" | <math>\mathrm{h}\!</math>
 +
| width="16%" | <math>\mathrm{i}~\!</math>
 +
| width="16%" | <math>\mathrm{j}\!</math>
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
\mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C}
 +
\\[3pt]
 +
\downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C}
 +
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
\mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C}
 +
\\[3pt]
 +
\downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{C} & \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B}
 +
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
\mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C}
 +
\\[3pt]
 +
\downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C} & \mathrm{A}
 +
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
\mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C}
 +
\\[3pt]
 +
\downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{A} & \mathrm{C} & \mathrm{B}
 +
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
\mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C}
 +
\\[3pt]
 +
\downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{C} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{A}
 +
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
 
<math>\begin{matrix}
\operatorname{e}
+
\mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C}
& = & \operatorname{A}:\operatorname{A}
+
\\[3pt]
& + & \operatorname{B}:\operatorname{B}
+
\downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow
& + & \operatorname{C}:\operatorname{C}
+
\\[6pt]
\\[4pt]
+
\mathrm{B} & \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{C}
\operatorname{f}
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
& = & \operatorname{A}:\operatorname{C}
 
& + & \operatorname{B}:\operatorname{A}
 
& + & \operatorname{C}:\operatorname{B}
 
\\[4pt]
 
\operatorname{g}
 
& = & \operatorname{A}:\operatorname{B}
 
& + & \operatorname{B}:\operatorname{C}
 
& + & \operatorname{C}:\operatorname{A}
 
\\[4pt]
 
\operatorname{h}
 
& = & \operatorname{A}:\operatorname{A}
 
& + & \operatorname{B}:\operatorname{C}
 
& + & \operatorname{C}:\operatorname{B}
 
\\[4pt]
 
\operatorname{i}
 
& = & \operatorname{A}:\operatorname{C}
 
& + & \operatorname{B}:\operatorname{B}
 
& + & \operatorname{C}:\operatorname{A}
 
\\[4pt]
 
\operatorname{j}
 
& = & \operatorname{A}:\operatorname{B}
 
& + & \operatorname{B}:\operatorname{A}
 
& + & \operatorname{C}:\operatorname{C}
 
\end{matrix}</math>
 
 
|}
 
|}
  
I have without stopping to think about it written out this natural representation of <math>S_3\!</math> in the style that comes most naturally to me, to wit, the "right" way, whereby an ordered pair configured as <math>X:Y\!</math> constitutes the turning of <math>X\!</math> into <math>Y.\!</math>  It is possible that the next time we check in with CSP that we will have to adjust our sense of direction, but that will be an easy enough bridge to cross when we come to it.
+
<br>
  
==Note 21==
+
Here is the operation table for <math>S_3,\!</math> given in abstract fashion:
  
To construct the regular representations of <math>S_3,\!</math> we begin with the data of its operation table:
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
 
 
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
 
 
| align="center" |
 
| align="center" |
 
<pre>
 
<pre>
Table 1.  Symmetric Group S_3
+
Symmetric Group S_3
 
o-------------------------------------------------o
 
o-------------------------------------------------o
 
|                                                |
 
|                                                |
Line 3,658: Line 3,637:
 
|}
 
|}
  
Just by way of staying clear about what we are doing, let's return to the recipe that we worked out before:
+
By the way, we will meet with the symmetric group <math>S_3~\!</math> again when we return to take up the study of Peirce's early paper "On a Class of Multiple Algebras" (CP 3.324&ndash;327), and also his late unpublished work "The Simplest Mathematics" (1902) (CP 4.227&ndash;323), with particular reference to the section that treats of "Trichotomic Mathematics" (CP 4.307&ndash;323).
  
It is part of the definition of a group that the 3-adic relation <math>L \subseteq G^3</math> is actually a function <math>L : G \times G \to G.</math>  It is from this functional perspective that we can see an easy way to derive the two regular representations.
+
==Note 20==
  
Since we have a function of the type <math>L : G \times G \to G,</math> we can define a couple of substitution operators:
+
By way of collecting a short-term pay-off for all the work &mdash; not to mention all the peirce-spiration &mdash; that we sweated out over the regular representations of the Klein 4-group <math>V_4,\!</math> let us write out as quickly as possible in ''relative form'' a minimal budget of representations of the symmetric group on three letters, <math>S_3 = \mathrm{Sym}(3).\!</math> After doing the usual bit of compare and contrast among these divers representations, we will have enough concrete material beneath our abstract belts to tackle a few of the presently obscur'd details of Peirce's early "Algebra + Logic" papers.
  
# <math>\operatorname{Sub}(x, (\underline{~~}, y))</math> puts any specified <math>x\!</math> into the empty slot of the rheme <math>(\underline{~~}, y),</math> with the effect of producing the saturated rheme <math>(x, y)\!</math> that evaluates to <math>x \cdot y.</math>
+
<br>
# <math>\operatorname{Sub}(x, (y, \underline{~~}))</math> puts any specified <math>x\!</math> into the empty slot of the rheme <math>(y, \underline{~~}),</math> with the effect of producing the saturated rheme <math>(y, x)\!</math> that evaluates to <math>y \cdot x.</math>
 
  
In (1) we consider the effects of each <math>x\!</math> in its practical bearing on contexts of the form <math>(\underline{~~}, y),</math> as <math>y\!</math> ranges over <math>G,\!</math> and the effects are such that <math>x\!</math> takes <math>(\underline{~~}, y)</math> into <math>x \cdot y,</math> for <math>y\!</math> in <math>G,\!</math> all of which is notated as <math>x = \{ (y : x \cdot y) ~|~ y \in G \}.</math>  The pairs <math>(y : x \cdot y)</math> can be found by picking an <math>x\!</math> from the left margin of the group operation table and considering its effects on each <math>y\!</math> in turn as these run along the right margin.  This produces the ''regular ante-representation'' of <math>S_3,\!</math> like so:
+
{| align="center" border="1" cellpadding="8" cellspacing="0" style="background:#f8f8ff; text-align:center; width:90%"
 
+
|+ <math>\text{Permutation Substitutions in}~ \mathrm{Sym} \{ \mathrm{A}, \mathrm{B}, \mathrm{C} \}\!</math>
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
|- style="background:#f0f0ff"
 +
| width="16%" | <math>\mathrm{e}\!</math>
 +
| width="16%" | <math>\mathrm{f}\!</math>
 +
| width="16%" | <math>\mathrm{g}\!</math>
 +
| width="16%" | <math>\mathrm{h}\!</math>
 +
| width="16%" | <math>\mathrm{i}~\!</math>
 +
| width="16%" | <math>\mathrm{j}\!</math>
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
\mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C}
 +
\\[3pt]
 +
\downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C}
 +
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
\mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C}
 +
\\[3pt]
 +
\downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{C} & \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B}
 +
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
\mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C}
 +
\\[3pt]
 +
\downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C} & \mathrm{A}
 +
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 
|
 
|
<math>\begin{array}{*{13}{c}}
+
<math>\begin{matrix}
\operatorname{e}
+
\mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C}
& = & \operatorname{e}:\operatorname{e}
+
\\[3pt]
& + & \operatorname{f}:\operatorname{f}
+
\downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow
& + & \operatorname{g}:\operatorname{g}
+
\\[6pt]
& + & \operatorname{h}:\operatorname{h}
+
\mathrm{A} & \mathrm{C} & \mathrm{B}
& + & \operatorname{i}:\operatorname{i}
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
& + & \operatorname{j}:\operatorname{j}
+
|
\\[4pt]
+
<math>\begin{matrix}
\operatorname{f}
+
\mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C}
& = & \operatorname{e}:\operatorname{f}
+
\\[3pt]
& + & \operatorname{f}:\operatorname{g}
+
\downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow
& + & \operatorname{g}:\operatorname{e}
+
\\[6pt]
& + & \operatorname{h}:\operatorname{j}
+
\mathrm{C} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{A}
& + & \operatorname{i}:\operatorname{h}
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
& + & \operatorname{j}:\operatorname{i}
+
|
\\[4pt]
+
<math>\begin{matrix}
\operatorname{g}
+
\mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C}
& = & \operatorname{e}:\operatorname{g}
+
\\[3pt]
& + & \operatorname{f}:\operatorname{e}
+
\downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow
& + & \operatorname{g}:\operatorname{f}
+
\\[6pt]
& + & \operatorname{h}:\operatorname{i}
+
\mathrm{B} & \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{C}
& + & \operatorname{i}:\operatorname{j}
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
& + & \operatorname{j}:\operatorname{h}
 
\\[4pt]
 
\operatorname{h}
 
& = & \operatorname{e}:\operatorname{h}
 
& + & \operatorname{f}:\operatorname{i}
 
& + & \operatorname{g}:\operatorname{j}
 
& + & \operatorname{h}:\operatorname{e}
 
& + & \operatorname{i}:\operatorname{f}
 
& + & \operatorname{j}:\operatorname{g}
 
\\[4pt]
 
\operatorname{i}
 
& = & \operatorname{e}:\operatorname{i}
 
& + & \operatorname{f}:\operatorname{j}
 
& + & \operatorname{g}:\operatorname{h}
 
& + & \operatorname{h}:\operatorname{g}
 
& + & \operatorname{i}:\operatorname{e}
 
& + & \operatorname{j}:\operatorname{f}
 
\\[4pt]
 
\operatorname{j}
 
& = & \operatorname{e}:\operatorname{j}
 
& + & \operatorname{f}:\operatorname{h}
 
& + & \operatorname{g}:\operatorname{i}
 
& + & \operatorname{h}:\operatorname{f}
 
& + & \operatorname{i}:\operatorname{g}
 
& + & \operatorname{j}:\operatorname{e}
 
\end{array}</math>
 
 
|}
 
|}
  
In (2) we consider the effects of each <math>x\!</math> in its practical bearing on contexts of the form <math>(y, \underline{~~}),</math> as <math>y\!</math> ranges over <math>G,\!</math> and the effects are such that <math>x\!</math> takes <math>(y, \underline{~~})</math> into <math>y \cdot x,</math> for <math>y\!</math> in <math>G,\!</math> all of which is notated as <math>x = \{ (y : y \cdot x) ~|~ y \in G \}.</math>  The pairs <math>(y : y \cdot x)</math> can be found by picking an <math>x\!</math> on the right margin of the group operation table and considering its effects on each <math>y\!</math> in turn as these run along the left margin.  This generates the ''regular post-representation'' of <math>S_3,\!</math> like so:
+
<br>
 +
 
 +
Writing this table in relative form generates the following natural representation of <math>S_3.\!</math>
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="10" width="90%"
|
+
| align="center" |
<math>\begin{array}{*{13}{c}}
+
<math>\begin{matrix}
\operatorname{e}
+
\mathrm{e}
& = & \operatorname{e}:\operatorname{e}
+
& = & \mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{A}
& + & \operatorname{f}:\operatorname{f}
+
& + & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{B}
& + & \operatorname{g}:\operatorname{g}
+
& + & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C}
& + & \operatorname{h}:\operatorname{h}
 
& + & \operatorname{i}:\operatorname{i}
 
& + & \operatorname{j}:\operatorname{j}
 
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{f}
+
\mathrm{f}
& = & \operatorname{e}:\operatorname{f}
+
& = & \mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{C}
& + & \operatorname{f}:\operatorname{g}
+
& + & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{A}
& + & \operatorname{g}:\operatorname{e}
+
& + & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{B}
& + & \operatorname{h}:\operatorname{i}
 
& + & \operatorname{i}:\operatorname{j}
 
& + & \operatorname{j}:\operatorname{h}
 
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{g}
+
\mathrm{g}
& = & \operatorname{e}:\operatorname{g}
+
& = & \mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{B}
& + & \operatorname{f}:\operatorname{e}
+
& + & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{C}
& + & \operatorname{g}:\operatorname{f}
+
& + & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{A}
& + & \operatorname{h}:\operatorname{j}
 
& + & \operatorname{i}:\operatorname{h}
 
& + & \operatorname{j}:\operatorname{i}
 
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{h}
+
\mathrm{h}
& = & \operatorname{e}:\operatorname{h}
+
& = & \mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{A}
& + & \operatorname{f}:\operatorname{j}
+
& + & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{C}
& + & \operatorname{g}:\operatorname{i}
+
& + & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{B}
& + & \operatorname{h}:\operatorname{e}
 
& + & \operatorname{i}:\operatorname{g}
 
& + & \operatorname{j}:\operatorname{f}
 
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{i}
+
\mathrm{i}
& = & \operatorname{e}:\operatorname{i}
+
& = & \mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{C}
& + & \operatorname{f}:\operatorname{h}
+
& + & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{B}
& + & \operatorname{g}:\operatorname{j}
+
& + & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{A}
& + & \operatorname{h}:\operatorname{f}
 
& + & \operatorname{i}:\operatorname{e}
 
& + & \operatorname{j}:\operatorname{g}
 
 
\\[4pt]
 
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{j}
+
\mathrm{j}
& = & \operatorname{e}:\operatorname{j}
+
& = & \mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{B}
& + & \operatorname{f}:\operatorname{i}
+
& + & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{A}
& + & \operatorname{g}:\operatorname{h}
+
& + & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C}
& + & \operatorname{h}:\operatorname{g}
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
& + & \operatorname{i}:\operatorname{f}
 
& + & \operatorname{j}:\operatorname{e}
 
\end{array}</math>
 
 
|}
 
|}
  
If the ante-rep looks different from the post-rep, it is just as it should be, as <math>S_3\!</math> is non-abelian (non-commutative), and so the two representations differ in the details of their practical effects, though, of course, being representations of the same abstract group, they must be isomorphic.
+
I have without stopping to think about it written out this natural representation of <math>S_3~\!</math> in the style that comes most naturally to me, to wit, the "right" way, whereby an ordered pair configured as <math>X:Y\!</math> constitutes the turning of <math>X\!</math> into <math>Y.\!</math>  It is possible that the next time we check in with CSP that we will have to adjust our sense of direction, but that will be an easy enough bridge to cross when we come to it.
  
==Note 22==
+
==Note 21==
  
{| cellpadding="2" cellspacing="2" width="100%"
+
To construct the regular representations of <math>S_3,\!</math> we begin with the data of its operation table:
| width="50%" | &nbsp;
 
| width="50%" |
 
the way of heaven and earth<br>
 
is to be long continued<br>
 
in their operation<br>
 
without stopping
 
|-
 
| height="50px" | &nbsp;
 
| valign="top"  | &mdash; i ching, hexagram 32
 
|}
 
  
You may be wondering what happened to the announced subject of ''Differential Logic'', and if you think that we have been taking a slight ''excursion'' &mdash; to use my favorite euphemism for ''digression'' &mdash; my reply to the charge of a scenic rout would need to be both "yes and no".  What happened was this.  At the sign-post marked by Sigil 7, we made the observation that the shift operators <math>\operatorname{E}_{ij}\!</math> form a transformation group that acts on the propositions of the form <math>f : \mathbb{B}^2 \to \mathbb{B}.</math>  Now group theory is a very attractive subject, but it did not really have the effect of drawing us so far off our initial course as you may at first think.  For one thing, groups, in particular, the groups that have come to be named after the Norwegian mathematician Marius Sophus Lie, have turned out to be of critical utility in the solution of differential equations.  For another thing, group operations afford us examples of triadic relations that have been extremely well-studied over the years, and this provides us with quite a bit of guidance in the study of sign relations, another class of triadic relations of significance for logical studies, in our brief acquaintance with which we have scarcely even started to break the ice.  Finally, I could hardly avoid taking up the connection between group representations, a very generic class of logical models, and the all-important pragmatic maxim.
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
 
+
|
* [http://www-history.mcs.st-andrews.ac.uk/Biographies/Lie.html Biographical Data for Marius Sophus Lie (1842&ndash;1899)]
 
 
 
==Note 23==
 
 
 
{| cellpadding="2" cellspacing="2" width="100%"
 
| width="50%" | &nbsp;
 
| width="50%" |
 
Bein' on the twenty-third of June,<br>
 
&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;As I sat weaving all at my loom,<br>
 
Bein' on the twenty-third of June,<br>
 
&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;As I sat weaving all at my loom,<br>
 
I heard a thrush, singing on yon bush,<br>
 
&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;And the song she sang was The Jug of Punch.<br>
 
|}
 
 
 
We've seen a couple of groups, <math>V_4\!</math> and <math>S_3,\!</math> represented in various ways, and we've seen their representations presented in a variety of different manners.  Let us look at one other stylistic variant for presenting a representation that is frequently seen, the so-called ''matrix representation'' of a group.
 
 
 
Recalling the manner of our acquaintance with the symmetric group <math>S_3,\!</math> we began with the ''bigraph'' (bipartite graph) picture of its natural representation as the set of all permutations or substitutions on the set <math>X = \{ A, B, C \}.\!</math>
 
 
 
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
 
| align="center" |
 
 
<pre>
 
<pre>
Table 1.  Permutations or Substitutions in Sym {A, B, C}
+
Symmetric Group S_3
o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o
+
o-------------------------------------------------o
|         |         |         |         |         |         |
+
|                                                 |
|   e   |   f   |   g    |   h    |   i    |   j    |
+
|                       ^                        |
|         |         |         |         |         |         |
+
|                     e / \ e                    |
o=========o=========o=========o=========o=========o=========o
+
|                     /  \                      |
|         |         |        |         |         |         |
+
|                     /  e \                    |
A B C | A B C | A B C | A B C | A B C  |  A B C |
+
|                 f / \  / \ f                  |
|         |         |         |        |        |        |
+
|                   /  \ /  \                  |
| | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | |
+
|                 /  f  \  f  \                  |
v v v | v v v | v v v | v v v | v v v | v v v  |
+
|               g / \  / \  / \ g              |
|         |         |         |         |         |         |
+
|               /  \ /  \ /  \                |
A B C | C A B | B C A A C B | C B A B A C |
+
|               /  g  \  g  \  g  \              |
|         |         |         |         |         |         |
+
|           h / \  / \  / \  / \ h            |
o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o
+
|            /  \ /  \ /  \ /  \            |
</pre>
+
|           /  h  \  e  \  e  \  h  \            |
|}
+
|        i / \  / \  / \  / \  / \ i         |
 
+
|         /  \ /  \ /  \ /  \ /  \          |
Then we rewrote these permutations &mdash; being functions <math>f : X \to X</math> they can also be recognized as being 2-adic relations <math>f \subseteq X \times X</math> &mdash; in ''relative form'', in effect, in the manner to which Peirce would have made us accustomed had he been given a relative half-a-chance:
+
|         / i \ i \ f \ j \ i \        |
 
+
|     j / \  / \  / \  / \  / \  / \ j      |
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
|       /  \ /  \ /  \ /  \ /  \ /  \      |
|
+
|     (  j \  j \ j \ i \ h \ j )      |
<math>\begin{matrix}
+
|       \  / \  / \  / \  / \  / \  /      |
\operatorname{e}
+
|       \ /  \ /  \ /  \ /  \ /  \ /        |
& = & \operatorname{A}:\operatorname{A}
+
|         \ h \ h \ e \ j \ i /        |
& + & \operatorname{B}:\operatorname{B}
+
|         \  / \  / \  / \  / \  /          |
& + & \operatorname{C}:\operatorname{C}
+
|           \ /  \ /  \ /  \ /  \ /          |
\\[4pt]
+
|           \  i  \  g  \  f  \  h  /            |
\operatorname{f}
+
|             \  / \  / \  / \  /            |
& = & \operatorname{A}:\operatorname{C}
+
|             \ /  \ /  \ /  \ /              |
& + & \operatorname{B}:\operatorname{A}
+
|               \ f \ e \ g /              |
& + & \operatorname{C}:\operatorname{B}
+
|                \  / \  / \  /                |
\\[4pt]
+
|                \ /  \ /  \ /                |
\operatorname{g}
+
|                  \ g \ f /                  |
& = & \operatorname{A}:\operatorname{B}
+
|                  \  / \  /                  |
& + & \operatorname{B}:\operatorname{C}
+
|                    \ /  \ /                    |
& + & \operatorname{C}:\operatorname{A}
+
|                    \ e /                    |
\\[4pt]
+
|                     \  /                      |
\operatorname{h}
+
|                       \ /                      |
& = & \operatorname{A}:\operatorname{A}
+
|                       v                        |
& + & \operatorname{B}:\operatorname{C}
+
|                                                 |
& + & \operatorname{C}:\operatorname{B}
+
o-------------------------------------------------o
\\[4pt]
+
</pre>
\operatorname{i}
+
|}
& = & \operatorname{A}:\operatorname{C}
+
 
& + & \operatorname{B}:\operatorname{B}
+
Just by way of staying clear about what we are doing, let's return to the recipe that we worked out before:
& + & \operatorname{C}:\operatorname{A}
+
 
\\[4pt]
+
It is part of the definition of a group that the 3-adic relation <math>L \subseteq G^3\!</math> is actually a function <math>L : G \times G \to G.\!</math> It is from this functional perspective that we can see an easy way to derive the two regular representations.
\operatorname{j}
+
 
& = & \operatorname{A}:\operatorname{B}
+
Since we have a function of the type <math>L : G \times G \to G,\!</math> we can define a couple of substitution operators:
& + & \operatorname{B}:\operatorname{A}
+
 
& + & \operatorname{C}:\operatorname{C}
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
\end{matrix}</math>
+
| valign="top" | 1.
|}
+
| <math>\mathrm{Sub}(x, (\underline{~~}, y))\!</math> puts any specified <math>x\!</math> into the empty slot of the rheme <math>(\underline{~~}, y),\!</math> with the effect of producing the saturated rheme <math>(x, y)\!</math> that evaluates to <math>x \cdot y.\!</math>
 
+
|-
These days one is much more likely to encounter the natural representation of <math>S_3\!</math> in the form of a ''linear representation'', that is, as a family of linear transformations that map the elements of a suitable vector space into each other, all of which would in turn usually be represented by a set of matrices like these:
+
| valign="top" | 2.
 
+
| <math>\mathrm{Sub}(x, (y, \underline{~~}))\!</math> puts any specified <math>x\!</math> into the empty slot of the rheme <math>(y, \underline{~~}),\!</math> with the effect of producing the saturated rheme <math>(y, x)\!</math> that evaluates to <math>y \cdot x.\!</math>
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
|}
| align="center" |
+
 
<pre>
+
In (1) we consider the effects of each <math>x\!</math> in its practical bearing on contexts of the form <math>(\underline{~~}, y),\!</math> as <math>y\!</math> ranges over <math>G,\!</math> and the effects are such that <math>x\!</math> takes <math>(\underline{~~}, y)\!</math> into <math>x \cdot y,\!</math> for <math>y\!</math> in <math>G,\!</math> all of which is notated as <math>x = \{ (y : x \cdot y) ~|~ y \in G \}.\!</math>  The pairs <math>(y : x \cdot y)\!</math> can be found by picking an <math>x\!</math> from the left margin of the group operation table and considering its effects on each <math>y\!</math> in turn as these run along the right margin.  This produces the ''regular ante-representation'' of <math>S_3,\!</math> like so:
Table 2.  Matrix Representations of Permutations in Sym(3)
 
o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o
 
|        |        |        |        |        |        |
 
|    e    |    f    |    g    |    h    |    i    |    j    |
 
|        |        |        |        |        |        |
 
o=========o=========o=========o=========o=========o=========o
 
|        |        |        |        |        |        |
 
|  1 0 0  |  0 0 1  |  0 1 0  |  1 0 0  |  0 0 1  |  0 1 0  |
 
|  0 1 0  |  1 0 0  |  0 0 1  |  0 0 1  |  0 1 0  |  1 0 0  |
 
|  0 0 1  |  0 1 0  |  1 0 0  |  0 1 0  |  1 0 0  |  0 0 1  |
 
|        |        |        |        |        |        |
 
o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o
 
</pre>
 
|}
 
 
 
The key to the mysteries of these matrices is revealed by noting that their coefficient entries are arrayed and overlaid on a place-mat marked like so:
 
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
 
|
 
|
<math>\begin{bmatrix}
+
<math>\begin{array}{*{13}{c}}
\mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{A} &
+
\mathrm{e}
\mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{B} &
+
& = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{e}
\mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{C}
+
& + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{f}
\\
+
& + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{g}
\mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{A} &
+
& + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{h}
\mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{B} &
+
& + & \mathrm{i}:\mathrm{i}
\mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{C}
+
& + & \mathrm{j}:\mathrm{j}
\\
+
\\[4pt]
\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{A} &
+
\mathrm{f}
\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{B} &
+
& = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{f}
\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C}
+
& + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{g}
\end{bmatrix}</math>
+
& + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{e}
 +
& + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{j}
 +
& + & \mathrm{i}:\mathrm{h}
 +
& + & \mathrm{j}:\mathrm{i}
 +
\\[4pt]
 +
\mathrm{g}
 +
& = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{g}
 +
& + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{e}
 +
& + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{f}
 +
& + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{i}
 +
& + & \mathrm{i}:\mathrm{j}
 +
& + & \mathrm{j}:\mathrm{h}
 +
\\[4pt]
 +
\mathrm{h}
 +
& = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{h}
 +
& + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{i}
 +
& + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{j}
 +
& + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{e}
 +
& + & \mathrm{i}:\mathrm{f}
 +
& + & \mathrm{j}:\mathrm{g}
 +
\\[4pt]
 +
\mathrm{i}
 +
& = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{i}
 +
& + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{j}
 +
& + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{h}
 +
& + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{g}
 +
& + & \mathrm{i}:\mathrm{e}
 +
& + & \mathrm{j}:\mathrm{f}
 +
\\[4pt]
 +
\mathrm{j}
 +
& = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{j}
 +
& + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{h}
 +
& + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{i}
 +
& + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{f}
 +
& + & \mathrm{i}:\mathrm{g}
 +
& + & \mathrm{j}:\mathrm{e}
 +
\end{array}\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  
Of course, the place-settings of convenience at different symposia may vary.
+
In (2) we consider the effects of each <math>x\!</math> in its practical bearing on contexts of the form <math>(y, \underline{~~}),\!</math> as <math>y\!</math> ranges over <math>G,\!</math> and the effects are such that <math>x\!</math> takes <math>(y, \underline{~~})\!</math> into <math>y \cdot x,\!</math> for <math>y\!</math> in <math>G,\!</math> all of which is notated as <math>x = \{ (y : y \cdot x) ~|~ y \in G \}.\!</math>  The pairs <math>(y : y \cdot x)~\!</math> can be found by picking an <math>x\!</math> on the right margin of the group operation table and considering its effects on each <math>y\!</math> in turn as these run along the left margin.  This generates the ''regular post-representation'' of <math>S_3,\!</math> like so:
  
==Note 24==
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{array}{*{13}{c}}
 +
\mathrm{e}
 +
& = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{e}
 +
& + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{f}
 +
& + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{g}
 +
& + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{h}
 +
& + & \mathrm{i}:\mathrm{i}
 +
& + & \mathrm{j}:\mathrm{j}
 +
\\[4pt]
 +
\mathrm{f}
 +
& = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{f}
 +
& + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{g}
 +
& + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{e}
 +
& + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{i}
 +
& + & \mathrm{i}:\mathrm{j}
 +
& + & \mathrm{j}:\mathrm{h}
 +
\\[4pt]
 +
\mathrm{g}
 +
& = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{g}
 +
& + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{e}
 +
& + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{f}
 +
& + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{j}
 +
& + & \mathrm{i}:\mathrm{h}
 +
& + & \mathrm{j}:\mathrm{i}
 +
\\[4pt]
 +
\mathrm{h}
 +
& = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{h}
 +
& + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{j}
 +
& + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{i}
 +
& + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{e}
 +
& + & \mathrm{i}:\mathrm{g}
 +
& + & \mathrm{j}:\mathrm{f}
 +
\\[4pt]
 +
\mathrm{i}
 +
& = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{i}
 +
& + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{h}
 +
& + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{j}
 +
& + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{f}
 +
& + & \mathrm{i}:\mathrm{e}
 +
& + & \mathrm{j}:\mathrm{g}
 +
\\[4pt]
 +
\mathrm{j}
 +
& = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{j}
 +
& + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{i}
 +
& + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{h}
 +
& + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{g}
 +
& + & \mathrm{i}:\mathrm{f}
 +
& + & \mathrm{j}:\mathrm{e}
 +
\end{array}\!</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
If the ante-rep looks different from the post-rep, it is just as it should be, as <math>S_3~\!</math> is non-abelian (non-commutative), and so the two representations differ in the details of their practical effects, though, of course, being representations of the same abstract group, they must be isomorphic.
 +
 
 +
==Note 22==
  
 
{| cellpadding="2" cellspacing="2" width="100%"
 
{| cellpadding="2" cellspacing="2" width="100%"
 
| width="50%" | &nbsp;
 
| width="50%" | &nbsp;
 
| width="50%" |
 
| width="50%" |
In the beginning was the three-pointed star,<br>
+
the way of heaven and earth<br>
One smile of light across the empty face;<br>
+
is to be long continued<br>
One bough of bone across the rooting air,<br>
+
in their operation<br>
The substance forked that marrowed the first sun;<br>
+
without stopping
And, burning ciphers on the round of space,<br>
 
Heaven and hell mixed as they spun.
 
 
|-
 
|-
| &nbsp;
+
| height="50px" | &nbsp;
| &mdash; Dylan Thomas, "In The Beginning", Verse 1
+
| valign="top"  | &mdash; i ching, hexagram 32
 
|}
 
|}
  
I'm afrayed that this thread is just bound to keep encountering its manifold of tensuous distractions, but I'd like to try and return now to the topic of inquiry, espectrally viewed in differential aspect.
+
You may be wondering what happened to the announced subject of ''Differential Logic'', and if you think that we have been taking a slight ''excursion'' &mdash; to use my favorite euphemism for ''digression'' &mdash; my reply to the charge of a scenic rout would need to be both "yes and no".  What happened was this.  At the sign-post marked by Sigil 7, we made the observation that the shift operators <math>\mathrm{E}_{ij}\!</math> form a transformation group that acts on the propositions of the form <math>f : \mathbb{B}^2 \to \mathbb{B}.\!</math>  Now group theory is a very attractive subject, but it did not really have the effect of drawing us so far off our initial course as you may at first think.  For one thing, groups, in particular, the groups that have come to be named after the Norwegian mathematician Marius Sophus Lie, have turned out to be of critical utility in the solution of differential equations.  For another thing, group operations afford us examples of triadic relations that have been extremely well-studied over the years, and this provides us with quite a bit of guidance in the study of sign relations, another class of triadic relations of significance for logical studies, in our brief acquaintance with which we have scarcely even started to break the ice.  Finally, I could hardly avoid taking up the connection between group representations, a very generic class of logical models, and the all-important pragmatic maxim.
 +
 
 +
* [http://www-history.mcs.st-andrews.ac.uk/Biographies/Lie.html Biographical Data for Marius Sophus Lie (1842&ndash;1899)]
  
Here's one picture of how it begins, one angle on the point of departure:
+
==Note 23==
  
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
{| cellpadding="2" cellspacing="2" width="100%"
| align="center" |
+
| width="50%" | &nbsp;
<pre>
+
| width="50%" |
o-----------------------------------------------------------o
+
Bein' on the twenty-third of June,<br>
|                                                          |
+
&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;As I sat weaving all at my loom,<br>
|                                                          |
+
Bein' on the twenty-third of June,<br>
|                      o-------------o                      |
+
&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;As I sat weaving all at my loom,<br>
|                    /              \                     |
+
I heard a thrush, singing on yon bush,<br>
|                    /                \                   |
+
&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;And the song she sang was The Jug of Punch.<br>
|                  /                  \                   |
+
|}
|                  /                    \                  |
+
 
|                 /                      \                |
+
We've seen a couple of groups, <math>V_4\!</math> and <math>S_3,\!</math> represented in various ways, and we've seen their representations presented in a variety of different manners.  Let us look at one other stylistic variant for presenting a representation that is frequently seen, the so-called ''matrix representation'' of a group.
|               o                        o                |
+
 
|                |                        |                |
+
Recalling the manner of our acquaintance with the symmetric group <math>S_3,\!</math> we began with the ''bigraph'' (bipartite graph) picture of its natural representation as the set of all permutations or substitutions on the set <math>X = \{ \mathrm{A}, \mathrm{B}, \mathrm{C} \}.\!</math>
|               |                        |                |
+
 
|               |      Observation      |                |
+
<br>
|               |                        |                |
+
 
|               |                         |                |
+
{| align="center" border="1" cellpadding="8" cellspacing="0" style="background:#f8f8ff; text-align:center; width:90%"
|            o--o----------o  o----------o--o            |
+
|+ <math>\text{Permutation Substitutions in}~ \mathrm{Sym} \{ \mathrm{A}, \mathrm{B}, \mathrm{C} \}\!</math>
|           /    \         \ /         /    \            |
+
|- style="background:#f0f0ff"
|           /      \   d_I ^  o  ^ d_E  /     \          |
+
| width="16%" | <math>\mathrm{e}\!</math>
|         /        \       \/ \/      /        \         |
+
| width="16%" | <math>\mathrm{f}\!</math>
|        /          \     /\ /\     /          \         |
+
| width="16%" | <math>\mathrm{g}\!</math>
|        /            \   /  @  \   /            \       |
+
| width="16%" | <math>\mathrm{h}\!</math>
|      o              o--o---|---o--o              o      |
+
| width="16%" | <math>\mathrm{i}~\!</math>
|      |                |  |  |                |      |
+
| width="16%" | <math>\mathrm{j}\!</math>
|      |                |  v  |                |      |
+
|-
|      |  Expectation  |  d_O  |    Intention    |      |
+
|
|      |                |      |                |      |
+
<math>\begin{matrix}
|      |                |      |                |      |
+
\mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C}
|      o                o      o                o      |
+
\\[3pt]
|        \                 \     /                /        |
+
\downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow
|        \                 \   /                /        |
+
\\[6pt]
|          \                 \ /                /          |
+
\mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C}
|          \                 o                /          |
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
|            \               / \               /           |
+
|
|            o-------------o  o-------------o            |
+
<math>\begin{matrix}
|                                                          |
+
\mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C}
|                                                          |
+
\\[3pt]
o-----------------------------------------------------------o
+
\downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow
</pre>
+
\\[6pt]
|}
+
\mathrm{C} & \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B}
 
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
From what we must assume was a state of Unconscious Nirvana (UN), since we do not acutely become conscious until after we are exiled from that garden of our blissful innocence, where our Expectations, our Intentions, our Observations all subsist in a state of perfect harmony, one with every barely perceived other, something intrudes on that scene of paradise to knock us out of that blessed isle and to trouble our countenance forever after at the retrospect thereof.
+
|
 
+
<math>\begin{matrix}
The least disturbance, it being provident and prudent both to take that first up, will arise in just one of three ways, in accord with the mode of discord that importunes on our equanimity, whether it is Expectation, Intention, Observation that incipiently incites the riot, departing as it will from congruence with the other two modes of being.
+
\mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C}
 
+
\\[3pt]
In short, we cross just one of the three lines that border on the center, or perhaps it is better to say that the objective situation transits one of the chordal bounds of harmony, for the moment marked as <math>\operatorname{d}_E, \operatorname{d}_I, \operatorname{d}_O</math> to note the fact one's Expectation, Intention, Observation, respectively, is the mode that we duly indite as the one that's sounding the sour note.
+
\downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow
 
+
\\[6pt]
{| align="center" cellpadding="6" width="90%"
+
\mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C} & \mathrm{A}
| A difference between Expectation and Observation is experienced as a ''Surprise'', a phenomenon that calls for an Explanation.
+
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
\mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C}
 +
\\[3pt]
 +
\downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{A} & \mathrm{C} & \mathrm{B}
 +
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
\mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C}
 +
\\[3pt]
 +
\downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{C} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{A}
 +
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
\mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C}
 +
\\[3pt]
 +
\downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow
 +
\\[6pt]
 +
\mathrm{B} & \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{C}
 +
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
<br>
 +
 
 +
Then we rewrote these permutations &mdash; being functions <math>f : X \to X\!</math> they can also be recognized as being 2-adic relations <math>f \subseteq X \times X\!</math> &mdash; in ''relative form'', in effect, in the manner to which Peirce would have made us accustomed had he been given a relative half-a-chance:
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
\mathrm{e}
 +
& = & \mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{A}
 +
& + & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{B}
 +
& + & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C}
 +
\\[4pt]
 +
\mathrm{f}
 +
& = & \mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{C}
 +
& + & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{A}
 +
& + & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{B}
 +
\\[4pt]
 +
\mathrm{g}
 +
& = & \mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{B}
 +
& + & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{C}
 +
& + & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{A}
 +
\\[4pt]
 +
\mathrm{h}
 +
& = & \mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{A}
 +
& + & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{C}
 +
& + & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{B}
 +
\\[4pt]
 +
\mathrm{i}
 +
& = & \mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{C}
 +
& + & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{B}
 +
& + & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{A}
 +
\\[4pt]
 +
\mathrm{j}
 +
& = & \mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{B}
 +
& + & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{A}
 +
& + & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C}
 +
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
These days one is much more likely to encounter the natural representation of <math>S_3~\!</math> in the form of a ''linear representation'', that is, as a family of linear transformations that map the elements of a suitable vector space into each other, all of which would in turn usually be represented by a set of matrices like these:
 +
 
 +
<br>
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" border="1" cellpadding="8" cellspacing="0" style="background:#f8f8ff; text-align:center; width:90%"
 +
|+ <math>\text{Matrix Representations of Permutations in}~ \mathrm{Sym}(3)\!</math>
 +
|- style="background:#f0f0ff"
 +
| width="16%" | <math>\mathrm{e}\!</math>
 +
| width="16%" | <math>\mathrm{f}\!</math>
 +
| width="16%" | <math>\mathrm{g}\!</math>
 +
| width="16%" | <math>\mathrm{h}\!</math>
 +
| width="16%" | <math>\mathrm{i}~\!</math>
 +
| width="16%" | <math>\mathrm{j}\!</math>
 +
|-
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
1 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 1 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 1
 +
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
0 & 0 & 1
 +
\\
 +
1 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 1 & 0
 +
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
0 & 1 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 1
 +
\\
 +
1 & 0 & 0
 +
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
1 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 1
 +
\\
 +
0 & 1 & 0
 +
\end{matrix}~\!</math>
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
0 & 0 & 1
 +
\\
 +
0 & 1 & 0
 +
\\
 +
1 & 0 & 0
 +
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{matrix}
 +
0 & 1 & 0
 +
\\
 +
1 & 0 & 0
 +
\\
 +
0 & 0 & 1
 +
\end{matrix}\!</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
<br>
 +
 
 +
The key to the mysteries of these matrices is revealed by noting that their coefficient entries are arrayed and overlaid on a place-mat marked like so:
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
 +
|
 +
<math>\begin{bmatrix}
 +
\mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{A} &
 +
\mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{B} &
 +
\mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{C}
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{A} &
 +
\mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{B} &
 +
\mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{C}
 +
\\
 +
\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{A} &
 +
\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{B} &
 +
\mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C}
 +
\end{bmatrix}\!</math>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
Of course, the place-settings of convenience at different symposia may vary.
 +
 
 +
==Note 24==
 +
 
 +
{| cellpadding="2" cellspacing="2" width="100%"
 +
| width="50%" | &nbsp;
 +
| width="50%" |
 +
In the beginning was the three-pointed star,<br>
 +
One smile of light across the empty face;<br>
 +
One bough of bone across the rooting air,<br>
 +
The substance forked that marrowed the first sun;<br>
 +
And, burning ciphers on the round of space,<br>
 +
Heaven and hell mixed as they spun.
 +
|-
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
| &mdash; Dylan Thomas, "In The Beginning", Verse 1
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
I'm afrayed that this thread is just bound to keep encountering its manifold of tensuous distractions, but I'd like to try and return now to the topic of inquiry, espectrally viewed in differential aspect.
 +
 
 +
Here's one picture of how it begins, one angle on the point of departure:
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
 +
|
 +
<pre>
 +
o-----------------------------------------------------------o
 +
|                                                          |
 +
|                                                          |
 +
|                      o-------------o                      |
 +
|                    /              \                    |
 +
|                    /                \                    |
 +
|                  /                  \                  |
 +
|                  /                    \                  |
 +
|                /                      \                |
 +
|                o                        o                |
 +
|                |                        |                |
 +
|                |                        |                |
 +
|                |      Observation      |                |
 +
|                |                        |                |
 +
|                |                        |                |
 +
|            o--o----------o  o----------o--o            |
 +
|            /    \          \ /          /    \            |
 +
|          /      \  d_I ^  o  ^ d_E  /      \          |
 +
|          /        \      \/ \/      /        \          |
 +
|        /          \      /\ /\      /          \        |
 +
|        /            \    /  @  \    /            \        |
 +
|      o              o--o---|---o--o              o      |
 +
|      |                |  |  |                |      |
 +
|      |                |  v  |                |      |
 +
|      |  Expectation  |  d_O  |    Intention    |      |
 +
|      |                |      |                |      |
 +
|      |                |      |                |      |
 +
|      o                o      o                o      |
 +
|        \                \    /                /        |
 +
|        \                \  /                /        |
 +
|          \                \ /                /          |
 +
|          \                o                /          |
 +
|            \              / \              /            |
 +
|            o-------------o  o-------------o            |
 +
|                                                          |
 +
|                                                          |
 +
o-----------------------------------------------------------o
 +
</pre>
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
From what we must assume was a state of Unconscious Nirvana (UN), since we do not acutely become conscious until after we are exiled from that garden of our blissful innocence, where our Expectations, our Intentions, our Observations all subsist in a state of perfect harmony, one with every barely perceived other, something intrudes on that scene of paradise to knock us out of that blessed isle and to trouble our countenance forever after at the retrospect thereof.
 +
 
 +
The least disturbance, it being provident and prudent both to take that first up, will arise in just one of three ways, in accord with the mode of discord that importunes on our equanimity, whether it is Expectation, Intention, Observation that incipiently incites the riot, departing as it will from congruence with the other two modes of being.
 +
 
 +
In short, we cross just one of the three lines that border on the center, or perhaps it is better to say that the objective situation transits one of the chordal bounds of harmony, for the moment marked as <math>\mathrm{d}_E, \mathrm{d}_I, \mathrm{d}_O\!</math> to note the fact one's Expectation, Intention, Observation, respectively, is the mode that we duly indite as the one that's sounding the sour note.
 +
 
 +
{| align="center" cellspacing="10"
 +
| A difference between Expectation and Observation is experienced as a ''Surprise'', a phenomenon that calls for an Explanation.
 +
|-
 +
| A discrepancy between Intention and Observation is experienced as a ''Problem'', a situation that calls for a Plan of Action.
 +
|-
 +
| A disparity between Expectation and Intention has no obvious name &mdash; I remember once thinking of a term that I thought was apt at the time, but I can't recall what it was, nor find the notes where I recorded it.
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
At any rate, the modes of experiencing a surprising phenomenon or a problematic situation, as described just now, are already complex modalities, and will need to be analyzed further if we want to relate them to the minimal changes <math>\mathrm{d}_E, \mathrm{d}_I, \mathrm{d}_O.\!</math>  Let me think about that for a little while and see what transpires.
 +
 
 +
==Note 25==
 +
 
 +
{| cellpadding="2" cellspacing="2" width="100%"
 +
| width="50%" | &nbsp;
 +
| width="50%" |
 +
In the beginning was the pale signature,<br>
 +
Three-syllabled and starry as the smile;<br>
 +
And after came the imprints on the water,<br>
 +
Stamp of the minted face upon the moon;<br>
 +
The blood that touched the crosstree and the grail<br>
 +
Touched the first cloud and left a sign.
 +
|-
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
| &mdash; Dylan Thomas, "In The Beginning", Verse 2
 +
|}
 +
 
 +
==Note 26==
 +
 
 +
{| cellpadding="2" cellspacing="2" width="100%"
 +
| width="50%" | &nbsp;
 +
| width="50%" |
 +
In the beginning was the mounting fire<br>
 +
That set alight the weathers from a spark,<br>
 +
A three-eyed, red-eyed spark, blunt as a flower;<br>
 +
Life rose and spouted from the rolling seas,<br>
 +
Burst in the roots, pumped from the earth and rock<br>
 +
The secret oils that drive the grass.
 
|-
 
|-
| A discrepancy between Intention and Observation is experienced as a ''Problem'', a situation that calls for a Plan of Action.
+
| &nbsp;
|-
+
| &mdash; Dylan Thomas, "In The Beginning", Verse 3
| A disparity between Expectation and Intention has no obvious name &mdash; I remember once thinking of a term that I thought was apt at the time, but I can't recall what it was, nor find the notes where I recorded it.
 
 
|}
 
|}
  
At any rate, the modes of experiencing a surprising phenomenon or a problematic situation, as described just now, are already complex modalities, and will need to be analyzed further if we want to relate them to the minimal changes <math>\operatorname{d}_E, \operatorname{d}_I, \operatorname{d}_O.</math>  Let me think about that for a little while and see what transpires.
+
==Document History==
 
 
==Note 25==
 
 
 
{| cellpadding="2" cellspacing="2" width="100%"
 
| width="50%" | &nbsp;
 
| width="50%" |
 
In the beginning was the pale signature,<br>
 
Three-syllabled and starry as the smile;<br>
 
And after came the imprints on the water,<br>
 
Stamp of the minted face upon the moon;<br>
 
The blood that touched the crosstree and the grail<br>
 
Touched the first cloud and left a sign.
 
|-
 
| &nbsp;
 
| &mdash; Dylan Thomas, "In The Beginning", Verse 2
 
|}
 
 
 
==Note 26==
 
 
 
{| cellpadding="2" cellspacing="2" width="100%"
 
| width="50%" | &nbsp;
 
| width="50%" |
 
In the beginning was the mounting fire<br>
 
That set alight the weathers from a spark,<br>
 
A three-eyed, red-eyed spark, blunt as a flower;<br>
 
Life rose and spouted from the rolling seas,<br>
 
Burst in the roots, pumped from the earth and rock<br>
 
The secret oils that drive the grass.
 
|-
 
| &nbsp;
 
| &mdash; Dylan Thomas, "In The Beginning", Verse 3
 
|}
 
  
==Work Area==
+
===Differential Logic &bull; Ontology List 2002===
  
<pre>
+
* http://web.archive.org/web/20110612002240/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/thrd28.html#04040
problem about writing
+
# http://web.archive.org/web/20140406040004/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04040.html
 
+
# http://web.archive.org/web/20110612001949/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04041.html
  e  =  e:e  +  f:f  +  g:g  +  h:h
+
# http://web.archive.org/web/20110612010502/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04045.html
 +
# http://web.archive.org/web/20110612005212/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04046.html
 +
# http://web.archive.org/web/20110612001954/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04047.html
 +
# http://web.archive.org/web/20110612010620/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04048.html
 +
# http://web.archive.org/web/20110612010550/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04052.html
 +
# http://web.archive.org/web/20110612010724/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04054.html
 +
# http://web.archive.org/web/20110612000847/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04055.html
 +
# http://web.archive.org/web/20110612001959/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04067.html
 +
# http://web.archive.org/web/20110612010507/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04068.html
 +
# http://web.archive.org/web/20110612002014/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04069.html
 +
# http://web.archive.org/web/20110612010701/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04070.html
 +
# http://web.archive.org/web/20110612003540/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04072.html
 +
# http://web.archive.org/web/20110612005229/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04073.html
 +
# http://web.archive.org/web/20110610153117/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04074.html
 +
# http://web.archive.org/web/20110612010555/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04077.html
 +
# http://web.archive.org/web/20110612001918/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04079.html
 +
# http://web.archive.org/web/20110612005244/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04080.html
 +
# http://web.archive.org/web/20110612005249/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04268.html
 +
# http://web.archive.org/web/20110612010626/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04269.html
 +
# http://web.archive.org/web/20110612000853/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04272.html
 +
# http://web.archive.org/web/20110612010514/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04273.html
 +
# http://web.archive.org/web/20110612002235/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04290.html
  
no recursion intended
+
===Dynamics And Logic &bull; Inquiry List 2004===
need for a work-around
 
ways way explaining it away
 
  
action on signs not objects
+
* http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/thread.html#1400
 +
* http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-July/thread.html#1685
 +
# http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001400.html
 +
# http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001401.html
 +
# http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001402.html
 +
# http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001403.html
 +
# http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001404.html
 +
# http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001405.html
 +
# http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001406.html
 +
# http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001407.html
 +
# http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001408.html
 +
# http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001410.html
 +
# http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001411.html
 +
# http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001412.html
 +
# http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001413.html
 +
# http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001415.html
 +
# http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001416.html
 +
# http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001418.html
 +
# http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001419.html
 +
# http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001420.html
 +
# http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001421.html
 +
# http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001422.html
 +
# http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001423.html
 +
# http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001424.html
 +
# http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-July/001685.html
 +
# http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-July/001686.html
 +
# http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-July/001687.html
 +
# http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-July/001688.html
  
math def of rep
+
===Dynamics And Logic &bull; NKS Forum 2004===
</pre>
 
  
==Document History==
+
* http://forum.wolframscience.com/archive/topic/420.html
 +
* http://forum.wolframscience.com/printthread.php?threadid=420
 +
* http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?threadid=420
 +
# http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1282#post1282
 +
# http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1285#post1285
 +
# http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1289#post1289
 +
# http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1292#post1292
 +
# http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1293#post1293
 +
# http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1294#post1294
 +
# http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1296#post1296
 +
# http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1299#post1299
 +
# http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1301#post1301
 +
# http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1304#post1304
 +
# http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1307#post1307
 +
# http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1309#post1309
 +
# http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1311#post1311
 +
# http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1314#post1314
 +
# http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1315#post1315
 +
# http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1318#post1318
 +
# http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1321#post1321
 +
# http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1323#post1323
 +
# http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1326#post1326
 +
# http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1327#post1327
 +
# http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1330#post1330
 +
# http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1331#post1331
 +
# http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1598#post1598
 +
# http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1601#post1601
 +
# http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1602#post1602
 +
# http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1603#post1603
  
* http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/thrd28.html#04040
+
[[Category:Artificial Intelligence]]
# http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04040.html
+
[[Category:Boolean Algebra]]
# http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04041.html
+
[[Category:Boolean Functions]]
# http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04045.html
+
[[Category:Charles Sanders Peirce]]
# http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04046.html
+
[[Category:Combinatorics]]
# http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04047.html
+
[[Category:Computational Complexity]]
# http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04048.html
+
[[Category:Computer Science]]
# http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04052.html
+
[[Category:Cybernetics]]
# http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04054.html
+
[[Category:Differential Logic]]
# http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04055.html
+
[[Category:Equational Reasoning]]
# http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04067.html
+
[[Category:Formal Languages]]
# http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04068.html
+
[[Category:Formal Systems]]
# http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04069.html
+
[[Category:Graph Theory]]
# http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04070.html
+
[[Category:Inquiry]]
# http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04072.html
+
[[Category:Inquiry Driven Systems]]
# http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04073.html
+
[[Category:Knowledge Representation]]
# http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04074.html
+
[[Category:Logic]]
# http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04077.html
+
[[Category:Logical Graphs]]
# http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04079.html
+
[[Category:Mathematics]]
# http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04080.html
+
[[Category:Philosophy]]
# http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04268.html
+
[[Category:Propositional Calculus]]
# http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04269.html
+
[[Category:Semiotics]]
# http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04272.html
+
[[Category:Visualization]]
# http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04273.html
 
# http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04290.html
 

Latest revision as of 19:32, 11 December 2014

☆ The MathJax formatter is currently having problems rendering the text below. ☆
☆ Meanwhile, please see the InterSciWiki copy at Differential Logic : Sketch 2. ☆

Author: Jon Awbrey

Note. The present Sketch is largely superseded by the article “Differential Logic : Introduction” but I have preserved it here for the sake of the remaining ideas that have yet to be absorbed elsewhere.

Differential logic is the component of logic whose object is the description of variation — for example, the aspects of change, difference, distribution, and diversity — in universes of discourse that are subject to logical description. In formal logic, differential logic treats the principles that govern the use of a differential logical calculus, that is, a formal system with the expressive capacity to describe change and diversity in logical universes of discourse.

A simple example of a differential logical calculus is furnished by a differential propositional calculus. A differential propositional calculus is a propositional calculus extended by a set of terms for describing aspects of change and difference, for example, processes that take place in a universe of discourse or transformations that map a source universe into a target universe. This augments ordinary propositional calculus in the same way that the differential calculus of Leibniz and Newton augments the analytic geometry of Descartes.

Note 1

One of the first things that you can do, once you have a really decent calculus for boolean functions or propositional logic, whatever you want to call it, is to compute the differentials of these functions or propositions.

Now there are many ways to dance around this idea, and I feel like I have tried them all, before one gets down to acting on it, and there many issues of interpretation and justification that we will have to clear up after the fact, that is, before we can be sure that it all really makes any sense, but I think this time I'll just jump in, and show you the form in which this idea first came to me.

Start with a proposition of the form \(x ~\mathrm{and}~ y,\!\) which is graphed as two labels attached to a root node:

o---------------------------------------o
|                                       |
|                  x y                  |
|                   @                   |
|                                       |
o---------------------------------------o
|                x and y                |
o---------------------------------------o

Written as a string, this is just the concatenation "\(x~y\!\)".

The proposition \(xy\!\) may be taken as a boolean function \(f(x, y)\!\) having the abstract type \(f : \mathbb{B} \times \mathbb{B} \to \mathbb{B},\!\) where \(\mathbb{B} = \{ 0, 1 \}~\!\) is read in such a way that \(0\!\) means \(\mathrm{false}\!\) and \(1\!\) means \(\mathrm{true}.\!\)

In this style of graphical representation, the value \(\mathrm{true}\!\) looks like a blank label and the value \(\mathrm{false}\!\) looks like an edge.

o---------------------------------------o
|                                       |
|                                       |
|                   @                   |
|                                       |
o---------------------------------------o
|                 true                  |
o---------------------------------------o
o---------------------------------------o
|                                       |
|                   o                   |
|                   |                   |
|                   @                   |
|                                       |
o---------------------------------------o
|                 false                 |
o---------------------------------------o

Back to the proposition \(xy.~\!\) Imagine yourself standing in a fixed cell of the corresponding venn diagram, say, the cell where the proposition \(xy\!\) is true, as shown here:

Venn Diagram X And Y.jpg

Now ask yourself: What is the value of the proposition \(xy\!\) at a distance of \(\mathrm{d}x\!\) and \(\mathrm{d}y\!\) from the cell \(xy\!\) where you are standing?

Don't think about it — just compute:

o---------------------------------------o
|                                       |
|              dx o   o dy              |
|                / \ / \                |
|             x o---@---o y             |
|                                       |
o---------------------------------------o
|         (x + dx) and (y + dy)         |
o---------------------------------------o

To make future graphs easier to draw in ASCII, I will use devices like @=@=@ and o=o=o to identify several nodes into one, as in this next redrawing:

o---------------------------------------o
|                                       |
|              x  dx y  dy              |
|              o---o o---o              |
|               \  | |  /               |
|                \ | | /                |
|                 \| |/                 |
|                  @=@                  |
|                                       |
o---------------------------------------o
|         (x + dx) and (y + dy)         |
o---------------------------------------o

However you draw it, these expressions follow because the expression \(x + \mathrm{d}x,\!\) where the plus sign indicates addition in \(\mathbb{B},\!\) that is, addition modulo 2, and thus corresponds to the exclusive disjunction operation in logic, parses to a graph of the following form:

o---------------------------------------o
|                                       |
|                x    dx                |
|                 o---o                 |
|                  \ /                  |
|                   @                   |
|                                       |
o---------------------------------------o
|                 x + dx                |
o---------------------------------------o

Next question: What is the difference between the value of the proposition \(xy\!\) "over there" and the value of the proposition \(xy\!\) where you are, all expressed as general formula, of course? Here 'tis:

o---------------------------------------o
|                                       |
|        x  dx y  dy                    |
|        o---o o---o                    |
|         \  | |  /                     |
|          \ | | /                      |
|           \| |/         x y           |
|            o=o-----------o            |
|             \           /             |
|              \         /              |
|               \       /               |
|                \     /                |
|                 \   /                 |
|                  \ /                  |
|                   @                   |
|                                       |
o---------------------------------------o
|      ((x + dx) & (y + dy)) - xy       |
o---------------------------------------o

Oh, I forgot to mention: Computed over \(\mathbb{B},\!\) plus and minus are the very same operation. This will make the relationship between the differential and the integral parts of the resulting calculus slightly stranger than usual, but never mind that now.

Last question, for now: What is the value of this expression from your current standpoint, that is, evaluated at the point where \(xy\!\) is true? Well, substituting \(1\!\) for \(x\!\) and \(1\!\) for \(y\!\) in the graph amounts to the same thing as erasing those labels:

o---------------------------------------o
|                                       |
|           dx    dy                    |
|        o---o o---o                    |
|         \  | |  /                     |
|          \ | | /                      |
|           \| |/                       |
|            o=o-----------o            |
|             \           /             |
|              \         /              |
|               \       /               |
|                \     /                |
|                 \   /                 |
|                  \ /                  |
|                   @                   |
|                                       |
o---------------------------------------o
|      ((1 + dx) & (1 + dy)) - 1·1      |
o---------------------------------------o

And this is equivalent to the following graph:

o---------------------------------------o
|                                       |
|                dx   dy                |
|                 o   o                 |
|                  \ /                  |
|                   o                   |
|                   |                   |
|                   @                   |
|                                       |
o---------------------------------------o
|               dx or dy                |
o---------------------------------------o

Note 2

We have just met with the fact that the differential of the and is the or of the differentials.

\(x ~\mathrm{and}~ y \quad \xrightarrow{~\mathrm{Diff}~} \quad \mathrm{d}x ~\mathrm{or}~ \mathrm{d}y\!\)

o---------------------------------------o
|                                       |
|                             dx   dy   |
|                              o   o    |
|                               \ /     |
|                                o      |
|      x y                       |      |
|       @       --Diff-->        @      |
|                                       |
o---------------------------------------o
|      x y      --Diff-->   ((dx)(dy))  |
o---------------------------------------o

It will be necessary to develop a more refined analysis of that statement directly, but that is roughly the nub of it.

If the form of the above statement reminds you of De Morgan's rule, it is no accident, as differentiation and negation turn out to be closely related operations. Indeed, one can find discussions of logical difference calculus in the Boole–De Morgan correspondence and Peirce also made use of differential operators in a logical context, but the exploration of these ideas has been hampered by a number of factors, not the least of which being a syntax adequate to handle the complexity of expressions that evolve.

For my part, it was definitely a case of the calculus being smarter than the calculator thereof. The graphical pictures were catalytic in their power over my thinking process, leading me so quickly past so many obstructions that I did not have time to think about all of the difficulties that would otherwise have inhibited the derivation. It did eventually became necessary to write all this up in a linear script, and to deal with the various problems of interpretation and justification that I could imagine, but that took another 120 pages, and so, if you don't like this intuitive approach, then let that be your sufficient notice.

Let us run through the initial example again, this time attempting to interpret the formulas that develop at each stage along the way.

We begin with a proposition or a boolean function \(f(x, y) = xy.\!\)

Venn Diagram F = X And Y.jpg
Cactus Graph F = X And Y.jpg

A function like this has an abstract type and a concrete type. The abstract type is what we invoke when we write things like \(f : \mathbb{B} \times \mathbb{B} \to \mathbb{B}\!\) or \(f : \mathbb{B}^2 \to \mathbb{B}.\!\) The concrete type takes into account the qualitative dimensions or the "units" of the case, which can be explained as follows.

Let \(X\!\) be the set of values \(\{ \texttt{(} x \texttt{)},~ x \} ~=~ \{ \mathrm{not}~ x,~ x \}.\!\)
Let \(Y\!\) be the set of values \(\{ \texttt{(} y \texttt{)},~ y \} ~=~ \{ \mathrm{not}~ y,~ y \}.\!\)

Then interpret the usual propositions about \(x, y\!\) as functions of the concrete type \(f : X \times Y \to \mathbb{B}.\!\)

We are going to consider various operators on these functions. Here, an operator \(\mathrm{F}\!\) is a function that takes one function \(f\!\) into another function \(\mathrm{F}f.\!\)

The first couple of operators that we need to consider are logical analogues of those that occur in the classical finite difference calculus, namely:

The difference operator \(\Delta,\!\) written here as \(\mathrm{D}.\!\)
The enlargement" operator \(\Epsilon,\!\) written here as \(\mathrm{E}.\!\)

These days, \(\mathrm{E}\!\) is more often called the shift operator.

In order to describe the universe in which these operators operate, it is necessary to enlarge the original universe of discourse, passing from the space \(U = X \times Y\!\) to its differential extension, \(\mathrm{E}U,\!\) that has the following description:

\(\mathrm{E}U ~=~ U \times \mathrm{d}U ~=~ X \times Y \times \mathrm{d}X \times \mathrm{d}Y,\!\)

with

\(\mathrm{d}X = \{ \texttt{(} \mathrm{d}x \texttt{)}, \mathrm{d}x \}\!\)  and  \(\mathrm{d}Y = \{ \texttt{(} \mathrm{d}y \texttt{)}, \mathrm{d}y \}.\!\)

The interpretations of these new symbols can be diverse, but the easiest option for now is just to say that \(\mathrm{d}x\!\) means "change \(x\!\)" and \(\mathrm{d}y\!\) means "change \(y\!\)". To draw the differential extension \(\mathrm{E}U~\!\) of our present universe \(U = X \times Y\!\) as a venn diagram, it would take us four logical dimensions \(X, Y, \mathrm{d}X, \mathrm{d}Y,\!\) but we can project a suggestion of what it's about on the universe \(X \times Y\!\) by drawing arrows that cross designated borders, labeling the arrows as \(\mathrm{d}x\!\) when crossing the border between \(x\!\) and \(\texttt{(} x \texttt{)}\!\) and as \(\mathrm{d}y\!\) when crossing the border between \(y\!\) and \(\texttt{(} y \texttt{)},\!\) in either direction, in either case.

Venn Diagram X Y dX dY.jpg

Propositions can be formed on differential variables, or any combination of ordinary logical variables and differential logical variables, in all the same ways that propositions can be formed on ordinary logical variables alone. For instance, the proposition \(\texttt{(} \mathrm{d}x \texttt{(} \mathrm{d}y \texttt{))}\!\) may be read to say that \(\mathrm{d}x \Rightarrow \mathrm{d}y,\!\) in other words, there is "no change in \(x\!\) without a change in \(y\!\)".

Given the proposition \(f(x, y)\!\) in \(U = X \times Y,\!\) the (first order) enlargement of \(f\!\) is the proposition \(\mathrm{E}f\!\) in \(\mathrm{E}U~\!\) that is defined by the formula \(\mathrm{E}f(x, y, \mathrm{d}x, \mathrm{d}y) = f(x + \mathrm{d}x, y + \mathrm{d}y).\!\)

Applying the enlargement operator \(\mathrm{E}\!\) to the present example, \(f(x, y) = xy,\!\) we may compute the result as follows:

\(\mathrm{E}f(x, y, \mathrm{d}x, \mathrm{d}y) \quad = \quad (x + \mathrm{d}x)(y + \mathrm{d}y).\!\)

o---------------------------------------o
|                                       |
|              x  dx y  dy              |
|              o---o o---o              |
|               \  | |  /               |
|                \ | | /                |
|                 \| |/                 |
|                  @=@                  |
|                                       |
o---------------------------------------o
| Ef =       (x, dx) (y, dy)            |
o---------------------------------------o

Given the proposition \(f(x, y)\!\) in \(U = X \times Y,\!\) the (first order) difference of \(f\!\) is the proposition \(\mathrm{D}f~\!\) in \(\mathrm{E}U~\!\) that is defined by the formula \(\mathrm{D}f = \mathrm{E}f - f,\!\) that is, \(\mathrm{D}f(x, y, \mathrm{d}x, \mathrm{d}y) = f(x + \mathrm{d}x, y + \mathrm{d}y) - f(x, y).\!\)

In the example \(f(x, y) = xy,\!\) the result is:

\(\mathrm{D}f(x, y, \mathrm{d}x, \mathrm{d}y) \quad = \quad (x + \mathrm{d}x)(y + \mathrm{d}y) - xy.\!\)

o---------------------------------------o
|                                       |
|        x  dx y  dy                    |
|        o---o o---o                    |
|         \  | |  /                     |
|          \ | | /                      |
|           \| |/         x y           |
|            o=o-----------o            |
|             \           /             |
|              \         /              |
|               \       /               |
|                \     /                |
|                 \   /                 |
|                  \ /                  |
|                   @                   |
|                                       |
o---------------------------------------o
| Df =       ((x, dx)(y, dy), xy)       |
o---------------------------------------o

We did not yet go through the trouble to interpret this (first order) difference of conjunction fully, but were happy simply to evaluate it with respect to a single location in the universe of discourse, namely, at the point picked out by the singular proposition \(xy,\!\) that is, at the place where \(x = 1\!\) and \(y = 1.\!\) This evaluation is written in the form \(\mathrm{D}f|_{xy}\!\) or \(\mathrm{D}f|_{(1, 1)},\!\) and we arrived at the locally applicable law that is stated and illustrated as follows:

\(f(x, y) ~=~ xy ~=~ x ~\mathrm{and}~ y \quad \Rightarrow \quad \mathrm{D}f|_{xy} ~=~ \texttt{((} \mathrm{dx} \texttt{)(} \mathrm{d}y \texttt{))} ~=~ \mathrm{d}x ~\mathrm{or}~ \mathrm{d}y.\!\)

Venn Diagram Difference Conj At Conj.jpg
Cactus Graph Difference Conj At Conj.jpg

The picture shows the analysis of the inclusive disjunction \(\texttt{((} \mathrm{d}x \texttt{)(} \mathrm{d}y \texttt{))}\!\) into the following exclusive disjunction:

\(\mathrm{d}x ~\texttt{(} \mathrm{d}y \texttt{)} ~+~ \mathrm{d}y ~\texttt{(} \mathrm{d}x \texttt{)} ~+~ \mathrm{d}x ~\mathrm{d}y.\!\)

This resulting differential proposition may be interpreted to say "change \(x\!\) or change \(y\!\) or both". And this can be recognized as just what you need to do if you happen to find yourself in the center cell and desire a detailed description of ways to depart it.

Note 3

Last time we computed what will variously be called the difference map, the difference proposition, or the local proposition \(\mathrm{D}f_p\!\) for the proposition \(f(x, y) = xy\!\) at the point \(p\!\) where \(x = 1\!\) and \(y = 1.\!\)

In the universe \(U = X \times Y,\!\) the four propositions \(xy,~ x\texttt{(}y\texttt{)},~ \texttt{(}x\texttt{)}y,~ \texttt{(}x\texttt{)(}y\texttt{)}\!\) that indicate the "cells", or the smallest regions of the venn diagram, are called singular propositions. These serve as an alternative notation for naming the points \((1, 1),~ (1, 0),~ (0, 1),~ (0, 0),\!\) respectively.

Thus we can write \(\mathrm{D}f_p = \mathrm{D}f|p = \mathrm{D}f|(1, 1) = \mathrm{D}f|xy,\!\) so long as we know the frame of reference in force.

Sticking with the example \(f(x, y) = xy,\!\) let us compute the value of the difference proposition \(\mathrm{D}f~\!\) at all 4 points.

o---------------------------------------o
|                                       |
|        x  dx y  dy                    |
|        o---o o---o                    |
|         \  | |  /                     |
|          \ | | /                      |
|           \| |/         x y           |
|            o=o-----------o            |
|             \           /             |
|              \         /              |
|               \       /               |
|                \     /                |
|                 \   /                 |
|                  \ /                  |
|                   @                   |
|                                       |
o---------------------------------------o
| Df =      ((x, dx)(y, dy), xy)        |
o---------------------------------------o
o---------------------------------------o
|                                       |
|           dx    dy                    |
|        o---o o---o                    |
|         \  | |  /                     |
|          \ | | /                      |
|           \| |/                       |
|            o=o-----------o            |
|             \           /             |
|              \         /              |
|               \       /               |
|                \     /                |
|                 \   /                 |
|                  \ /                  |
|                   @                   |
|                                       |
o---------------------------------------o
| Df|xy =      ((dx)(dy))               |
o---------------------------------------o
o---------------------------------------o
|                                       |
|              o                        |
|           dx |  dy                    |
|        o---o o---o                    |
|         \  | |  /                     |
|          \ | | /         o            |
|           \| |/          |            |
|            o=o-----------o            |
|             \           /             |
|              \         /              |
|               \       /               |
|                \     /                |
|                 \   /                 |
|                  \ /                  |
|                   @                   |
|                                       |
o---------------------------------------o
| Df|x(y) =      (dx) dy                |
o---------------------------------------o
o---------------------------------------o
|                                       |
|        o                              |
|        |  dx    dy                    |
|        o---o o---o                    |
|         \  | |  /                     |
|          \ | | /         o            |
|           \| |/          |            |
|            o=o-----------o            |
|             \           /             |
|              \         /              |
|               \       /               |
|                \     /                |
|                 \   /                 |
|                  \ /                  |
|                   @                   |
|                                       |
o---------------------------------------o
| Df|(x)y =      dx (dy)                |
o---------------------------------------o
o---------------------------------------o
|                                       |
|        o     o                        |
|        |  dx |  dy                    |
|        o---o o---o                    |
|         \  | |  /                     |
|          \ | | /       o   o          |
|           \| |/         \ /           |
|            o=o-----------o            |
|             \           /             |
|              \         /              |
|               \       /               |
|                \     /                |
|                 \   /                 |
|                  \ /                  |
|                   @                   |
|                                       |
o---------------------------------------o
| Df|(x)(y) =     dx dy                 |
o---------------------------------------o

The easy way to visualize the values of these graphical expressions is just to notice the following equivalents:

o---------------------------------------o
|                                       |
|  x                                    |
|  o-o-o-...-o-o-o                      |
|   \           /                       |
|    \         /                        |
|     \       /                         |
|      \     /                x         |
|       \   /                 o         |
|        \ /                  |         |
|         @         =         @         |
|                                       |
o---------------------------------------o
|  (x, , ... , , )  =        (x)        |
o---------------------------------------o
o---------------------------------------o
|                                       |
|                o                      |
| x_1 x_2   x_k  |                      |
|  o---o-...-o---o                      |
|   \           /                       |
|    \         /                        |
|     \       /                         |
|      \     /                          |
|       \   /                           |
|        \ /             x_1 ... x_k    |
|         @         =         @         |
|                                       |
o---------------------------------------o
| (x_1, ..., x_k, ()) = x_1 · ... · x_k |
o---------------------------------------o

Laying out the arrows on the augmented venn diagram, one gets a picture of a differential vector field.

Venn Diagram Difference Conj.jpg

The Figure shows the points of the extended universe \(\mathrm{E}U = X \times Y \times \mathrm{d}X \times \mathrm{d}Y\!\) that satisfy the difference proposition \(\mathrm{D}f,\!\) namely, these:

\(\begin{array}{rcccc} 1. & x & y & \mathrm{d}x & \mathrm{d}y \\ 2. & x & y & \mathrm{d}x & (\mathrm{d}y) \\ 3. & x & y & (\mathrm{d}x) & \mathrm{d}y \\ 4. & x & (y) & (\mathrm{d}x) & \mathrm{d}y \\ 5. & (x) & y & \mathrm{d}x & (\mathrm{d}y) \\ 6. & (x) & (y) & \mathrm{d}x & \mathrm{d}y \end{array}\!\)

An inspection of these six points should make it easy to understand \(\mathrm{D}f~\!\) as telling you what you have to do from each point of \(U\!\) in order to change the value borne by the proposition \(f(x, y).\!\)

Note 4

We have been studying the action of the difference operator \(\mathrm{D},\!\) also known as the localization operator, on the proposition \(f : X \times Y \to \mathbb{B}\!\) that is commonly known as the conjunction \(x \cdot y.\!\) We described \(\mathrm{D}f~\!\) as a (first order) differential proposition, that is, a proposition of the type \(\mathrm{D}f : X \times Y \times \mathrm{d}X \times \mathrm{d}Y \to \mathbb{B}.\!\) Abstracting from the augmented venn diagram that illustrates how the models or satisfying interpretations of \(\mathrm{D}f~\!\) distribute within the extended universe \(\mathrm{E}U = X \times Y \times \mathrm{d}X \times \mathrm{d}Y,\!\) we can depict \(\mathrm{D}f~\!\) in the form of a digraph or directed graph, one whose points are labeled with the elements of \(U = X \times Y\!\) and whose arrows are labeled with the elements of \(\mathrm{d}U = \mathrm{d}X \times \mathrm{d}Y.\!\)

Directed Graph Difference Conj.jpg

\(\begin{array}{rcccccc} f & = & x & \cdot & y \'"`UNIQ-MathJax1-QINU`"' Amazing! =='"`UNIQ--h-7--QINU`"'Note 8== We have been contemplating functions of the type \(f : U \to \mathbb{B}\!\) and studying the action of the operators \(\mathrm{E}\!\) and \(\mathrm{D}\!\) on this family. These functions, that we may identify for our present aims with propositions, inasmuch as they capture their abstract forms, are logical analogues of scalar potential fields. These are the sorts of fields that are so picturesquely presented in elementary calculus and physics textbooks by images of snow-covered hills and parties of skiers who trek down their slopes like least action heroes. The analogous scene in propositional logic presents us with forms more reminiscent of plateaunic idylls, being all plains at one of two levels, the mesas of verity and falsity, as it were, with nary a niche to inhabit between them, restricting our options for a sporting gradient of downhill dynamics to just one of two: standing still on level ground or falling off a bluff.

We are still working well within the logical analogue of the classical finite difference calculus, taking in the novelties that the logical transmutation of familiar elements is able to bring to light. Soon we will take up several different notions of approximation relationships that may be seen to organize the space of propositions, and these will allow us to define several different forms of differential analysis applying to propositions. In time we will find reason to consider more general types of maps, having concrete types of the form \(X_1 \times \ldots \times X_k \to Y_1 \times \ldots \times Y_n\!\) and abstract types \(\mathbb{B}^k \to \mathbb{B}^n.\!\) We will think of these mappings as transforming universes of discourse into themselves or into others, in short, as transformations of discourse.

Before we continue with this intinerary, however, I would like to highlight another sort of differential aspect that concerns the boundary operator or the marked connective that serves as one of the two basic connectives in the cactus language for ZOL.

For example, consider the proposition \(f\!\) of concrete type \(f : X \times Y \times Z \to \mathbb{B}\!\) and abstract type \(f : \mathbb{B}^3 \to \mathbb{B}\!\) that is written \(\texttt{(} x, y, z \texttt{)}\!\) in cactus syntax. Taken as an assertion in what Peirce called the existential interpretation, \(\texttt{(} x, y, z \texttt{)}\!\) says that just one of \(x, y, z\!\) is false. It is useful to consider this assertion in relation to the conjunction \(xyz\!\) of the features that are engaged as its arguments. A venn diagram of \(\texttt{(} x, y, z \texttt{)}\!\) looks like this:

Minimal Negation Operator (x,y,z).jpg

In relation to the center cell indicated by the conjunction \(xyz,\!\) the region indicated by \(\texttt{(} x, y, z \texttt{)}\!\) is comprised of the adjacent or bordering cells. Thus they are the cells that are just across the boundary of the center cell, as if reached by way of Leibniz's minimal changes from the point of origin, here, \(xyz.\!\)

The same sort of boundary relationship holds for any cell of origin that one chooses to indicate. One way to indicate a cell is by forming a logical conjunction of positive and negative basis features, that is, by constructing an expression of the form \(e_1 \cdot \ldots \cdot e_k,\!\) where \(e_j = x_j ~\text{or}~ e_j = \texttt{(} x_j \texttt{)},\!\) for \(j = 1 ~\text{to}~ k.\!\) The proposition \(\texttt{(} e_1, \ldots, e_k \texttt{)}\!\) indicates the disjunctive region consisting of the cells that are just next door to \(e_1 \cdot \ldots \cdot e_k.\!\)

Note 9

Consider what effects that might conceivably have practical bearings you conceive the objects of your conception to have. Then, your conception of those effects is the whole of your conception of the object.

— Charles Sanders Peirce, "Issues of Pragmaticism", [CP 5.438]

One other subject that it would be opportune to mention at this point, while we have an object example of a mathematical group fresh in mind, is the relationship between the pragmatic maxim and what are commonly known in mathematics as representation principles. As it turns out, with regard to its formal characteristics, the pragmatic maxim unites the aspects of a representation principle with the attributes of what would ordinarily be known as a closure principle. We will consider the form of closure that is invoked by the pragmatic maxim on another occasion, focusing here and now on the topic of group representations.

Let us return to the example of the four-group \(V_4.\!\) We encountered this group in one of its concrete representations, namely, as a transformation group that acts on a set of objects, in this case a set of sixteen functions or propositions. Forgetting about the set of objects that the group transforms among themselves, we may take the abstract view of the group's operational structure, for example, in the form of the group operation table copied here:


\(\cdot\!\)

\(\mathrm{e}\!\)

\(\mathrm{f}\!\)

\(\mathrm{g}\!\)

\(\mathrm{h}\!\)

\(\mathrm{e}\!\) \(\mathrm{e}\!\) \(\mathrm{f}\!\) \(\mathrm{g}\!\) \(\mathrm{h}\!\)
\(\mathrm{f}\!\) \(\mathrm{f}\!\) \(\mathrm{e}\!\) \(\mathrm{h}\!\) \(\mathrm{g}\!\)
\(\mathrm{g}\!\) \(\mathrm{g}\!\) \(\mathrm{h}\!\) \(\mathrm{e}\!\) \(\mathrm{f}\!\)
\(\mathrm{h}\!\) \(\mathrm{h}\!\) \(\mathrm{g}\!\) \(\mathrm{f}\!\) \(\mathrm{e}\!\)


This operation table is abstractly the same as, or isomorphic to, the versions with the \(\mathrm{E}_{ij}\!\) operators and the \(\mathrm{T}_{ij}\!\) transformations that we discussed earlier. That is to say, the story is the same — only the names have been changed. An abstract group can have a multitude of significantly and superficially different representations. Even after we have long forgotten the details of the particular representation that we may have come in with, there are species of concrete representations, called the regular representations, that are always readily available, as they can be generated from the mere data of the abstract operation table itself.

To see how a regular representation is constructed from the abstract operation table, pick a group element at the top of the table and "consider its effects" on each of the group elements listed on the left. These effects may be recorded in one of the ways that Peirce often used, as a logical aggregate of elementary dyadic relatives, that is, as a logical disjunction or sum whose terms represent the \(\mathrm{input} : \mathrm{output}\!\) pairs that are produced by each group element in turn. This forms one of the two possible regular representations of the group, specifically, the one that is called the post-regular representation or the right regular representation. It has long been conventional to organize the terms of this logical sum in the form of a matrix:

Reading "\(+\!\)" as a logical disjunction:

\(\begin{matrix} \mathrm{G} & = & \mathrm{e} & + & \mathrm{f} & + & \mathrm{g} & + & \mathrm{h} \end{matrix}\!\)

And so, by expanding effects, we get:

\(\begin{matrix} \mathrm{G} & = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{e} & + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{f} & + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{g} & + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{h} \'"`UNIQ-MathJax2-QINU`"' is the relate, \(J\!\) is the correlate, and in our current example we read \(I:J,\!\) or more exactly, \(\mathit{n}_{ij} = 1,\!\) to say that \(I\!\) is a noder of \(J.\!\) This is the mode of reading that we call multiplying on the left.

In the algebraic, permutational, or transformational contexts of application, however, Peirce converts to the alternative mode of reading, although still calling \(I\!\) the relate and \(J\!\) the correlate, the elementary relative \(I:J\!\) now means that \(I\!\) gets changed into \(J.\!\) In this scheme of reading, the transformation \(\mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{B} + \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{C} + \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{A}\!\) is a permutation of the aggregate \(\mathbf{1} = \mathrm{A} + \mathrm{B} + \mathrm{C},\!\) or what we would now call the set \(\{ \mathrm{A}, \mathrm{B}, \mathrm{C} \},\!\) in particular, it is the permutation that is otherwise notated as follows:

\(\begin{Bmatrix} \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C} \\ \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C} & \mathrm{A} \end{Bmatrix}\!\)

This is consistent with the convention that Peirce uses in the paper "On a Class of Multiple Algebras" (CP 3.324–327).

Note 16

We have been contemplating the virtues and the utilities of the pragmatic maxim as a hermeneutic heuristic, specifically, as a principle of interpretation that guides us in finding a clarifying representation for a problematic corpus of symbols in terms of their actions on other symbols or their effects on the syntactic contexts in which we conceive to distribute them. I started off considering the regular representations of groups as constituting what appears to be one of the simplest possible applications of this overall principle of representation.

There are a few problems of implementation that have to be worked out in practice, most of which are cleared up by keeping in mind which of several possible conventions we have chosen to follow at a given time. But there does appear to remain this rather more substantial question:

  • Are the effects we seek relates or correlates, or does it even matter?

I will have to leave that question as it is for now, in hopes that a solution will evolve itself in time.

Note 17

There a big reasons and little reasons for caring about this humble example. The little reasons we find all under our feet. One big reason I can now quite blazonly enounce in the fashion of this not so subtle subtitle:

Obstacles to Applying the Pragmatic Maxim

No sooner do you get a good idea and try to apply it than you find that a motley array of obstacles arise.

It seems as if I am constantly lamenting the fact these days that people, and even admitted Peircean persons, do not in practice more consistently apply the maxim of pragmatism to the purpose for which it is purportedly intended by its author. That would be the clarification of concepts, or intellectual symbols, to the point where their inherent senses, or their lacks thereof, would be rendered manifest to all and sundry interpreters.

There are big obstacles and little obstacles to applying the pragmatic maxim. In good subgoaling fashion, I will merely mention a few of the bigger blocks, as if in passing, and then get down to the devilish details that immediately obstruct our way.

Obstacle 1
People do not always read the instructions very carefully. There is a tendency in readers of particular prior persuasions to blow the problem all out of proportion, to think that the maxim is meant to reveal the absolutely positive and the totally unique meaning of every preconception to which they might deign or elect to apply it. Reading the maxim with an even minimal attention, you can see that it promises no such finality of unindexed sense, but ties what you conceive to you. I have lately come to wonder at the tenacity of this misinterpretation. Perhaps people reckon that nothing less would be worth their attention. I am not sure. I can only say the achievement of more modest goals is the sort of thing on which our daily life depends, and there can be no final end to inquiry nor any ultimate community without a continuation of life, and that means life on a day to day basis. All of which only brings me back to the point of persisting with local meantime examples, because if we can't apply the maxim there, we can't apply it anywhere.

And now I need to go out of doors and weed my garden for a time …

Note 18

Obstacles to Applying the Pragmatic Maxim

Obstacle 2
Applying the pragmatic maxim, even with a moderate aim, can be hard. I think that my present example, deliberately impoverished as it is, affords us with an embarrassing richness of evidence of just how complex the simple can be.

All the better reason for me to see if I can finish it up before moving on.

Expressed most simply, the idea is to replace the question of what it is, which modest people know is far too difficult for them to answer right off, with the question of what it does, which most of us know a modicum about.

In the case of regular representations of groups we found a non-plussing surplus of answers to sort our way through. So let us track back one more time to see if we can learn any lessons that might carry over to more realistic cases.

Here is is the operation table of \(V_4\!\) once again:


\(\text{Klein Four-Group}~ V_4\!\)
\(\cdot\!\)

\(\mathrm{e}\!\)

\(\mathrm{f}\!\)

\(\mathrm{g}\!\)

\(\mathrm{h}\!\)

\(\mathrm{e}\!\) \(\mathrm{e}\!\) \(\mathrm{f}\!\) \(\mathrm{g}\!\) \(\mathrm{h}\!\)
\(\mathrm{f}\!\) \(\mathrm{f}\!\) \(\mathrm{e}\!\) \(\mathrm{h}\!\) \(\mathrm{g}\!\)
\(\mathrm{g}\!\) \(\mathrm{g}\!\) \(\mathrm{h}\!\) \(\mathrm{e}\!\) \(\mathrm{f}\!\)
\(\mathrm{h}\!\) \(\mathrm{h}\!\) \(\mathrm{g}\!\) \(\mathrm{f}\!\) \(\mathrm{e}\!\)


A group operation table is really just a device for recording a certain 3-adic relation, to be specific, the set of triples of the form \((x, y, z)\!\) satisfying the equation \(x \cdot y = z.\!\)

In the case of \(V_4 = (G, \cdot),\!\) where \(G\!\) is the underlying set \(\{ \mathrm{e}, \mathrm{f}, \mathrm{g}, \mathrm{h} \},\!\) we have the 3-adic relation \(L(V_4) \subseteq G \times G \times G\!\) whose triples are listed below:

\(\begin{matrix} (\mathrm{e}, \mathrm{e}, \mathrm{e}) & (\mathrm{e}, \mathrm{f}, \mathrm{f}) & (\mathrm{e}, \mathrm{g}, \mathrm{g}) & (\mathrm{e}, \mathrm{h}, \mathrm{h}) \\[6pt] (\mathrm{f}, \mathrm{e}, \mathrm{f}) & (\mathrm{f}, \mathrm{f}, \mathrm{e}) & (\mathrm{f}, \mathrm{g}, \mathrm{h}) & (\mathrm{f}, \mathrm{h}, \mathrm{g}) \\[6pt] (\mathrm{g}, \mathrm{e}, \mathrm{g}) & (\mathrm{g}, \mathrm{f}, \mathrm{h}) & (\mathrm{g}, \mathrm{g}, \mathrm{e}) & (\mathrm{g}, \mathrm{h}, \mathrm{f}) \\[6pt] (\mathrm{h}, \mathrm{e}, \mathrm{h}) & (\mathrm{h}, \mathrm{f}, \mathrm{g}) & (\mathrm{h}, \mathrm{g}, \mathrm{f}) & (\mathrm{h}, \mathrm{h}, \mathrm{e}) \end{matrix}\!\)

It is part of the definition of a group that the 3-adic relation \(L \subseteq G^3\!\) is actually a function \(L : G \times G \to G.\!\) It is from this functional perspective that we can see an easy way to derive the two regular representations. Since we have a function of the type \(L : G \times G \to G,\!\) we can define a couple of substitution operators:

1. \(\mathrm{Sub}(x, (\underline{~~}, y))\!\) puts any specified \(x\!\) into the empty slot of the rheme \((\underline{~~}, y),\!\) with the effect of producing the saturated rheme \((x, y)\!\) that evaluates to \(x \cdot y.\!\)
2. \(\mathrm{Sub}(x, (y, \underline{~~}))\!\) puts any specified \(x\!\) into the empty slot of the rheme \((y, \underline{~~}),\!\) with the effect of producing the saturated rheme \((y, x)\!\) that evaluates to \(y \cdot x.\!\)

In (1) we consider the effects of each \(x\!\) in its practical bearing on contexts of the form \((\underline{~~}, y),\!\) as \(y\!\) ranges over \(G,\!\) and the effects are such that \(x\!\) takes \((\underline{~~}, y)\!\) into \(x \cdot y,\!\) for \(y\!\) in \(G,\!\) all of which is notated as \(x = \{ (y : x \cdot y) ~|~ y \in G \}.\!\) The pairs \((y : x \cdot y)\!\) can be found by picking an \(x\!\) from the left margin of the group operation table and considering its effects on each \(y\!\) in turn as these run across the top margin. This aspect of pragmatic definition we recognize as the regular ante-representation:

\(\begin{matrix} \mathrm{e} & = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{e} & + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{f} & + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{g} & + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{h} \\[4pt] \mathrm{f} & = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{f} & + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{e} & + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{h} & + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{g} \\[4pt] \mathrm{g} & = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{g} & + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{h} & + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{e} & + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{f} \\[4pt] \mathrm{h} & = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{h} & + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{g} & + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{f} & + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{e} \end{matrix}\!\)

In (2) we consider the effects of each \(x\!\) in its practical bearing on contexts of the form \((y, \underline{~~}),\!\) as \(y\!\) ranges over \(G,\!\) and the effects are such that \(x\!\) takes \((y, \underline{~~})\!\) into \(y \cdot x,\!\) for \(y\!\) in \(G,\!\) all of which is notated as \(x = \{ (y : y \cdot x) ~|~ y \in G \}.\!\) The pairs \((y : y \cdot x)~\!\) can be found by picking an \(x\!\) from the top margin of the group operation table and considering its effects on each \(y\!\) in turn as these run down the left margin. This aspect of pragmatic definition we recognize as the regular post-representation:

\(\begin{matrix} \mathrm{e} & = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{e} & + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{f} & + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{g} & + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{h} \\[4pt] \mathrm{f} & = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{f} & + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{e} & + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{h} & + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{g} \\[4pt] \mathrm{g} & = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{g} & + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{h} & + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{e} & + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{f} \\[4pt] \mathrm{h} & = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{h} & + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{g} & + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{f} & + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{e} \end{matrix}\!\)

If the ante-rep looks the same as the post-rep, now that I'm writing them in the same dialect, that is because \(V_4\!\) is abelian (commutative), and so the two representations have the very same effects on each point of their bearing.

Note 19

So long as we're in the neighborhood, we might as well take in some more of the sights, for instance, the smallest example of a non-abelian (non-commutative) group. This is a group of six elements, say, \(G = \{ \mathrm{e}, \mathrm{f}, \mathrm{g}, \mathrm{h}, \mathrm{i}, \mathrm{j} \},\!\) with no relation to any other employment of these six symbols being implied, of course, and it can be most easily represented as the permutation group on a set of three letters, say, \(X = \{ A, B, C \},\!\) usually notated as \(G = \mathrm{Sym}(X)\!\) or more abstractly and briefly, as \(\mathrm{Sym}(3)\!\) or \(S_3.\!\) The next Table shows the intended correspondence between abstract group elements and the permutation or substitution operations in \(\mathrm{Sym}(X).\!\)


\(\text{Permutation Substitutions in}~ \mathrm{Sym} \{ \mathrm{A}, \mathrm{B}, \mathrm{C} \}\!\)
\(\mathrm{e}\!\) \(\mathrm{f}\!\) \(\mathrm{g}\!\) \(\mathrm{h}\!\) \(\mathrm{i}~\!\) \(\mathrm{j}\!\)

\(\begin{matrix} \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C} \\[3pt] \downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow \\[6pt] \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C} \end{matrix}\!\)

\(\begin{matrix} \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C} \\[3pt] \downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow \\[6pt] \mathrm{C} & \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} \end{matrix}\!\)

\(\begin{matrix} \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C} \\[3pt] \downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow \\[6pt] \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C} & \mathrm{A} \end{matrix}\!\)

\(\begin{matrix} \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C} \\[3pt] \downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow \\[6pt] \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{C} & \mathrm{B} \end{matrix}\!\)

\(\begin{matrix} \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C} \\[3pt] \downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow \\[6pt] \mathrm{C} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{A} \end{matrix}\!\)

\(\begin{matrix} \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C} \\[3pt] \downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow \\[6pt] \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{C} \end{matrix}\!\)


Here is the operation table for \(S_3,\!\) given in abstract fashion:

Symmetric Group S_3
o-------------------------------------------------o
|                                                 |
|                        ^                        |
|                     e / \ e                     |
|                      /   \                      |
|                     /  e  \                     |
|                  f / \   / \ f                  |
|                   /   \ /   \                   |
|                  /  f  \  f  \                  |
|               g / \   / \   / \ g               |
|                /   \ /   \ /   \                |
|               /  g  \  g  \  g  \               |
|            h / \   / \   / \   / \ h            |
|             /   \ /   \ /   \ /   \             |
|            /  h  \  e  \  e  \  h  \            |
|         i / \   / \   / \   / \   / \ i         |
|          /   \ /   \ /   \ /   \ /   \          |
|         /  i  \  i  \  f  \  j  \  i  \         |
|      j / \   / \   / \   / \   / \   / \ j      |
|       /   \ /   \ /   \ /   \ /   \ /   \       |
|      (  j  \  j  \  j  \  i  \  h  \  j  )      |
|       \   / \   / \   / \   / \   / \   /       |
|        \ /   \ /   \ /   \ /   \ /   \ /        |
|         \  h  \  h  \  e  \  j  \  i  /         |
|          \   / \   / \   / \   / \   /          |
|           \ /   \ /   \ /   \ /   \ /           |
|            \  i  \  g  \  f  \  h  /            |
|             \   / \   / \   / \   /             |
|              \ /   \ /   \ /   \ /              |
|               \  f  \  e  \  g  /               |
|                \   / \   / \   /                |
|                 \ /   \ /   \ /                 |
|                  \  g  \  f  /                  |
|                   \   / \   /                   |
|                    \ /   \ /                    |
|                     \  e  /                     |
|                      \   /                      |
|                       \ /                       |
|                        v                        |
|                                                 |
o-------------------------------------------------o

By the way, we will meet with the symmetric group \(S_3~\!\) again when we return to take up the study of Peirce's early paper "On a Class of Multiple Algebras" (CP 3.324–327), and also his late unpublished work "The Simplest Mathematics" (1902) (CP 4.227–323), with particular reference to the section that treats of "Trichotomic Mathematics" (CP 4.307–323).

Note 20

By way of collecting a short-term pay-off for all the work — not to mention all the peirce-spiration — that we sweated out over the regular representations of the Klein 4-group \(V_4,\!\) let us write out as quickly as possible in relative form a minimal budget of representations of the symmetric group on three letters, \(S_3 = \mathrm{Sym}(3).\!\) After doing the usual bit of compare and contrast among these divers representations, we will have enough concrete material beneath our abstract belts to tackle a few of the presently obscur'd details of Peirce's early "Algebra + Logic" papers.


\(\text{Permutation Substitutions in}~ \mathrm{Sym} \{ \mathrm{A}, \mathrm{B}, \mathrm{C} \}\!\)
\(\mathrm{e}\!\) \(\mathrm{f}\!\) \(\mathrm{g}\!\) \(\mathrm{h}\!\) \(\mathrm{i}~\!\) \(\mathrm{j}\!\)

\(\begin{matrix} \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C} \\[3pt] \downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow \\[6pt] \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C} \end{matrix}\!\)

\(\begin{matrix} \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C} \\[3pt] \downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow \\[6pt] \mathrm{C} & \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} \end{matrix}\!\)

\(\begin{matrix} \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C} \\[3pt] \downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow \\[6pt] \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C} & \mathrm{A} \end{matrix}\!\)

\(\begin{matrix} \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C} \\[3pt] \downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow \\[6pt] \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{C} & \mathrm{B} \end{matrix}\!\)

\(\begin{matrix} \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C} \\[3pt] \downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow \\[6pt] \mathrm{C} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{A} \end{matrix}\!\)

\(\begin{matrix} \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C} \\[3pt] \downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow \\[6pt] \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{C} \end{matrix}\!\)


Writing this table in relative form generates the following natural representation of \(S_3.\!\)

\(\begin{matrix} \mathrm{e} & = & \mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{A} & + & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{B} & + & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C} \\[4pt] \mathrm{f} & = & \mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{C} & + & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{A} & + & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{B} \\[4pt] \mathrm{g} & = & \mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{B} & + & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{C} & + & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{A} \\[4pt] \mathrm{h} & = & \mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{A} & + & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{C} & + & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{B} \\[4pt] \mathrm{i} & = & \mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{C} & + & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{B} & + & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{A} \\[4pt] \mathrm{j} & = & \mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{B} & + & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{A} & + & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C} \end{matrix}\!\)

I have without stopping to think about it written out this natural representation of \(S_3~\!\) in the style that comes most naturally to me, to wit, the "right" way, whereby an ordered pair configured as \(X:Y\!\) constitutes the turning of \(X\!\) into \(Y.\!\) It is possible that the next time we check in with CSP that we will have to adjust our sense of direction, but that will be an easy enough bridge to cross when we come to it.

Note 21

To construct the regular representations of \(S_3,\!\) we begin with the data of its operation table:

Symmetric Group S_3
o-------------------------------------------------o
|                                                 |
|                        ^                        |
|                     e / \ e                     |
|                      /   \                      |
|                     /  e  \                     |
|                  f / \   / \ f                  |
|                   /   \ /   \                   |
|                  /  f  \  f  \                  |
|               g / \   / \   / \ g               |
|                /   \ /   \ /   \                |
|               /  g  \  g  \  g  \               |
|            h / \   / \   / \   / \ h            |
|             /   \ /   \ /   \ /   \             |
|            /  h  \  e  \  e  \  h  \            |
|         i / \   / \   / \   / \   / \ i         |
|          /   \ /   \ /   \ /   \ /   \          |
|         /  i  \  i  \  f  \  j  \  i  \         |
|      j / \   / \   / \   / \   / \   / \ j      |
|       /   \ /   \ /   \ /   \ /   \ /   \       |
|      (  j  \  j  \  j  \  i  \  h  \  j  )      |
|       \   / \   / \   / \   / \   / \   /       |
|        \ /   \ /   \ /   \ /   \ /   \ /        |
|         \  h  \  h  \  e  \  j  \  i  /         |
|          \   / \   / \   / \   / \   /          |
|           \ /   \ /   \ /   \ /   \ /           |
|            \  i  \  g  \  f  \  h  /            |
|             \   / \   / \   / \   /             |
|              \ /   \ /   \ /   \ /              |
|               \  f  \  e  \  g  /               |
|                \   / \   / \   /                |
|                 \ /   \ /   \ /                 |
|                  \  g  \  f  /                  |
|                   \   / \   /                   |
|                    \ /   \ /                    |
|                     \  e  /                     |
|                      \   /                      |
|                       \ /                       |
|                        v                        |
|                                                 |
o-------------------------------------------------o

Just by way of staying clear about what we are doing, let's return to the recipe that we worked out before:

It is part of the definition of a group that the 3-adic relation \(L \subseteq G^3\!\) is actually a function \(L : G \times G \to G.\!\) It is from this functional perspective that we can see an easy way to derive the two regular representations.

Since we have a function of the type \(L : G \times G \to G,\!\) we can define a couple of substitution operators:

1. \(\mathrm{Sub}(x, (\underline{~~}, y))\!\) puts any specified \(x\!\) into the empty slot of the rheme \((\underline{~~}, y),\!\) with the effect of producing the saturated rheme \((x, y)\!\) that evaluates to \(x \cdot y.\!\)
2. \(\mathrm{Sub}(x, (y, \underline{~~}))\!\) puts any specified \(x\!\) into the empty slot of the rheme \((y, \underline{~~}),\!\) with the effect of producing the saturated rheme \((y, x)\!\) that evaluates to \(y \cdot x.\!\)

In (1) we consider the effects of each \(x\!\) in its practical bearing on contexts of the form \((\underline{~~}, y),\!\) as \(y\!\) ranges over \(G,\!\) and the effects are such that \(x\!\) takes \((\underline{~~}, y)\!\) into \(x \cdot y,\!\) for \(y\!\) in \(G,\!\) all of which is notated as \(x = \{ (y : x \cdot y) ~|~ y \in G \}.\!\) The pairs \((y : x \cdot y)\!\) can be found by picking an \(x\!\) from the left margin of the group operation table and considering its effects on each \(y\!\) in turn as these run along the right margin. This produces the regular ante-representation of \(S_3,\!\) like so:

\(\begin{array}{*{13}{c}} \mathrm{e} & = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{e} & + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{f} & + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{g} & + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{h} & + & \mathrm{i}:\mathrm{i} & + & \mathrm{j}:\mathrm{j} \\[4pt] \mathrm{f} & = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{f} & + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{g} & + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{e} & + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{j} & + & \mathrm{i}:\mathrm{h} & + & \mathrm{j}:\mathrm{i} \\[4pt] \mathrm{g} & = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{g} & + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{e} & + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{f} & + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{i} & + & \mathrm{i}:\mathrm{j} & + & \mathrm{j}:\mathrm{h} \\[4pt] \mathrm{h} & = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{h} & + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{i} & + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{j} & + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{e} & + & \mathrm{i}:\mathrm{f} & + & \mathrm{j}:\mathrm{g} \\[4pt] \mathrm{i} & = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{i} & + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{j} & + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{h} & + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{g} & + & \mathrm{i}:\mathrm{e} & + & \mathrm{j}:\mathrm{f} \\[4pt] \mathrm{j} & = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{j} & + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{h} & + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{i} & + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{f} & + & \mathrm{i}:\mathrm{g} & + & \mathrm{j}:\mathrm{e} \end{array}\!\)

In (2) we consider the effects of each \(x\!\) in its practical bearing on contexts of the form \((y, \underline{~~}),\!\) as \(y\!\) ranges over \(G,\!\) and the effects are such that \(x\!\) takes \((y, \underline{~~})\!\) into \(y \cdot x,\!\) for \(y\!\) in \(G,\!\) all of which is notated as \(x = \{ (y : y \cdot x) ~|~ y \in G \}.\!\) The pairs \((y : y \cdot x)~\!\) can be found by picking an \(x\!\) on the right margin of the group operation table and considering its effects on each \(y\!\) in turn as these run along the left margin. This generates the regular post-representation of \(S_3,\!\) like so:

\(\begin{array}{*{13}{c}} \mathrm{e} & = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{e} & + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{f} & + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{g} & + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{h} & + & \mathrm{i}:\mathrm{i} & + & \mathrm{j}:\mathrm{j} \\[4pt] \mathrm{f} & = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{f} & + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{g} & + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{e} & + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{i} & + & \mathrm{i}:\mathrm{j} & + & \mathrm{j}:\mathrm{h} \\[4pt] \mathrm{g} & = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{g} & + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{e} & + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{f} & + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{j} & + & \mathrm{i}:\mathrm{h} & + & \mathrm{j}:\mathrm{i} \\[4pt] \mathrm{h} & = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{h} & + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{j} & + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{i} & + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{e} & + & \mathrm{i}:\mathrm{g} & + & \mathrm{j}:\mathrm{f} \\[4pt] \mathrm{i} & = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{i} & + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{h} & + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{j} & + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{f} & + & \mathrm{i}:\mathrm{e} & + & \mathrm{j}:\mathrm{g} \\[4pt] \mathrm{j} & = & \mathrm{e}:\mathrm{j} & + & \mathrm{f}:\mathrm{i} & + & \mathrm{g}:\mathrm{h} & + & \mathrm{h}:\mathrm{g} & + & \mathrm{i}:\mathrm{f} & + & \mathrm{j}:\mathrm{e} \end{array}\!\)

If the ante-rep looks different from the post-rep, it is just as it should be, as \(S_3~\!\) is non-abelian (non-commutative), and so the two representations differ in the details of their practical effects, though, of course, being representations of the same abstract group, they must be isomorphic.

Note 22

 

the way of heaven and earth
is to be long continued
in their operation
without stopping

  — i ching, hexagram 32

You may be wondering what happened to the announced subject of Differential Logic, and if you think that we have been taking a slight excursion — to use my favorite euphemism for digression — my reply to the charge of a scenic rout would need to be both "yes and no". What happened was this. At the sign-post marked by Sigil 7, we made the observation that the shift operators \(\mathrm{E}_{ij}\!\) form a transformation group that acts on the propositions of the form \(f : \mathbb{B}^2 \to \mathbb{B}.\!\) Now group theory is a very attractive subject, but it did not really have the effect of drawing us so far off our initial course as you may at first think. For one thing, groups, in particular, the groups that have come to be named after the Norwegian mathematician Marius Sophus Lie, have turned out to be of critical utility in the solution of differential equations. For another thing, group operations afford us examples of triadic relations that have been extremely well-studied over the years, and this provides us with quite a bit of guidance in the study of sign relations, another class of triadic relations of significance for logical studies, in our brief acquaintance with which we have scarcely even started to break the ice. Finally, I could hardly avoid taking up the connection between group representations, a very generic class of logical models, and the all-important pragmatic maxim.

Note 23

 

Bein' on the twenty-third of June,
        As I sat weaving all at my loom,
Bein' on the twenty-third of June,
        As I sat weaving all at my loom,
I heard a thrush, singing on yon bush,
        And the song she sang was The Jug of Punch.

We've seen a couple of groups, \(V_4\!\) and \(S_3,\!\) represented in various ways, and we've seen their representations presented in a variety of different manners. Let us look at one other stylistic variant for presenting a representation that is frequently seen, the so-called matrix representation of a group.

Recalling the manner of our acquaintance with the symmetric group \(S_3,\!\) we began with the bigraph (bipartite graph) picture of its natural representation as the set of all permutations or substitutions on the set \(X = \{ \mathrm{A}, \mathrm{B}, \mathrm{C} \}.\!\)


\(\text{Permutation Substitutions in}~ \mathrm{Sym} \{ \mathrm{A}, \mathrm{B}, \mathrm{C} \}\!\)
\(\mathrm{e}\!\) \(\mathrm{f}\!\) \(\mathrm{g}\!\) \(\mathrm{h}\!\) \(\mathrm{i}~\!\) \(\mathrm{j}\!\)

\(\begin{matrix} \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C} \\[3pt] \downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow \\[6pt] \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C} \end{matrix}\!\)

\(\begin{matrix} \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C} \\[3pt] \downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow \\[6pt] \mathrm{C} & \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} \end{matrix}\!\)

\(\begin{matrix} \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C} \\[3pt] \downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow \\[6pt] \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C} & \mathrm{A} \end{matrix}\!\)

\(\begin{matrix} \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C} \\[3pt] \downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow \\[6pt] \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{C} & \mathrm{B} \end{matrix}\!\)

\(\begin{matrix} \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C} \\[3pt] \downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow \\[6pt] \mathrm{C} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{A} \end{matrix}\!\)

\(\begin{matrix} \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C} \\[3pt] \downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow \\[6pt] \mathrm{B} & \mathrm{A} & \mathrm{C} \end{matrix}\!\)


Then we rewrote these permutations — being functions \(f : X \to X\!\) they can also be recognized as being 2-adic relations \(f \subseteq X \times X\!\) — in relative form, in effect, in the manner to which Peirce would have made us accustomed had he been given a relative half-a-chance:

\(\begin{matrix} \mathrm{e} & = & \mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{A} & + & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{B} & + & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C} \\[4pt] \mathrm{f} & = & \mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{C} & + & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{A} & + & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{B} \\[4pt] \mathrm{g} & = & \mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{B} & + & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{C} & + & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{A} \\[4pt] \mathrm{h} & = & \mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{A} & + & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{C} & + & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{B} \\[4pt] \mathrm{i} & = & \mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{C} & + & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{B} & + & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{A} \\[4pt] \mathrm{j} & = & \mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{B} & + & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{A} & + & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C} \end{matrix}\!\)

These days one is much more likely to encounter the natural representation of \(S_3~\!\) in the form of a linear representation, that is, as a family of linear transformations that map the elements of a suitable vector space into each other, all of which would in turn usually be represented by a set of matrices like these:


\(\text{Matrix Representations of Permutations in}~ \mathrm{Sym}(3)\!\)
\(\mathrm{e}\!\) \(\mathrm{f}\!\) \(\mathrm{g}\!\) \(\mathrm{h}\!\) \(\mathrm{i}~\!\) \(\mathrm{j}\!\)

\(\begin{matrix} 1 & 0 & 0 \\ 0 & 1 & 0 \\ 0 & 0 & 1 \end{matrix}\!\)

\(\begin{matrix} 0 & 0 & 1 \\ 1 & 0 & 0 \\ 0 & 1 & 0 \end{matrix}\!\)

\(\begin{matrix} 0 & 1 & 0 \\ 0 & 0 & 1 \\ 1 & 0 & 0 \end{matrix}\!\)

\(\begin{matrix} 1 & 0 & 0 \\ 0 & 0 & 1 \\ 0 & 1 & 0 \end{matrix}~\!\)

\(\begin{matrix} 0 & 0 & 1 \\ 0 & 1 & 0 \\ 1 & 0 & 0 \end{matrix}\!\)

\(\begin{matrix} 0 & 1 & 0 \\ 1 & 0 & 0 \\ 0 & 0 & 1 \end{matrix}\!\)


The key to the mysteries of these matrices is revealed by noting that their coefficient entries are arrayed and overlaid on a place-mat marked like so:

\(\begin{bmatrix} \mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{A} & \mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{B} & \mathrm{A}\!:\!\mathrm{C} \\ \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{A} & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{B} & \mathrm{B}\!:\!\mathrm{C} \\ \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{A} & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{B} & \mathrm{C}\!:\!\mathrm{C} \end{bmatrix}\!\)

Of course, the place-settings of convenience at different symposia may vary.

Note 24

 

In the beginning was the three-pointed star,
One smile of light across the empty face;
One bough of bone across the rooting air,
The substance forked that marrowed the first sun;
And, burning ciphers on the round of space,
Heaven and hell mixed as they spun.

  — Dylan Thomas, "In The Beginning", Verse 1

I'm afrayed that this thread is just bound to keep encountering its manifold of tensuous distractions, but I'd like to try and return now to the topic of inquiry, espectrally viewed in differential aspect.

Here's one picture of how it begins, one angle on the point of departure:

o-----------------------------------------------------------o
|                                                           |
|                                                           |
|                      o-------------o                      |
|                     /               \                     |
|                    /                 \                    |
|                   /                   \                   |
|                  /                     \                  |
|                 /                       \                 |
|                o                         o                |
|                |                         |                |
|                |                         |                |
|                |       Observation       |                |
|                |                         |                |
|                |                         |                |
|             o--o----------o   o----------o--o             |
|            /    \          \ /          /    \            |
|           /      \   d_I ^  o  ^ d_E   /      \           |
|          /        \       \/ \/       /        \          |
|         /          \      /\ /\      /          \         |
|        /            \    /  @  \    /            \        |
|       o              o--o---|---o--o              o       |
|       |                 |   |   |                 |       |
|       |                 |   v   |                 |       |
|       |   Expectation   |  d_O  |    Intention    |       |
|       |                 |       |                 |       |
|       |                 |       |                 |       |
|       o                 o       o                 o       |
|        \                 \     /                 /        |
|         \                 \   /                 /         |
|          \                 \ /                 /          |
|           \                 o                 /           |
|            \               / \               /            |
|             o-------------o   o-------------o             |
|                                                           |
|                                                           |
o-----------------------------------------------------------o

From what we must assume was a state of Unconscious Nirvana (UN), since we do not acutely become conscious until after we are exiled from that garden of our blissful innocence, where our Expectations, our Intentions, our Observations all subsist in a state of perfect harmony, one with every barely perceived other, something intrudes on that scene of paradise to knock us out of that blessed isle and to trouble our countenance forever after at the retrospect thereof.

The least disturbance, it being provident and prudent both to take that first up, will arise in just one of three ways, in accord with the mode of discord that importunes on our equanimity, whether it is Expectation, Intention, Observation that incipiently incites the riot, departing as it will from congruence with the other two modes of being.

In short, we cross just one of the three lines that border on the center, or perhaps it is better to say that the objective situation transits one of the chordal bounds of harmony, for the moment marked as \(\mathrm{d}_E, \mathrm{d}_I, \mathrm{d}_O\!\) to note the fact one's Expectation, Intention, Observation, respectively, is the mode that we duly indite as the one that's sounding the sour note.

A difference between Expectation and Observation is experienced as a Surprise, a phenomenon that calls for an Explanation.
A discrepancy between Intention and Observation is experienced as a Problem, a situation that calls for a Plan of Action.
A disparity between Expectation and Intention has no obvious name — I remember once thinking of a term that I thought was apt at the time, but I can't recall what it was, nor find the notes where I recorded it.

At any rate, the modes of experiencing a surprising phenomenon or a problematic situation, as described just now, are already complex modalities, and will need to be analyzed further if we want to relate them to the minimal changes \(\mathrm{d}_E, \mathrm{d}_I, \mathrm{d}_O.\!\) Let me think about that for a little while and see what transpires.

Note 25

 

In the beginning was the pale signature,
Three-syllabled and starry as the smile;
And after came the imprints on the water,
Stamp of the minted face upon the moon;
The blood that touched the crosstree and the grail
Touched the first cloud and left a sign.

  — Dylan Thomas, "In The Beginning", Verse 2

Note 26

 

In the beginning was the mounting fire
That set alight the weathers from a spark,
A three-eyed, red-eyed spark, blunt as a flower;
Life rose and spouted from the rolling seas,
Burst in the roots, pumped from the earth and rock
The secret oils that drive the grass.

  — Dylan Thomas, "In The Beginning", Verse 3

Document History

Differential Logic • Ontology List 2002

  1. http://web.archive.org/web/20140406040004/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04040.html
  2. http://web.archive.org/web/20110612001949/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04041.html
  3. http://web.archive.org/web/20110612010502/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04045.html
  4. http://web.archive.org/web/20110612005212/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04046.html
  5. http://web.archive.org/web/20110612001954/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04047.html
  6. http://web.archive.org/web/20110612010620/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04048.html
  7. http://web.archive.org/web/20110612010550/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04052.html
  8. http://web.archive.org/web/20110612010724/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04054.html
  9. http://web.archive.org/web/20110612000847/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04055.html
  10. http://web.archive.org/web/20110612001959/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04067.html
  11. http://web.archive.org/web/20110612010507/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04068.html
  12. http://web.archive.org/web/20110612002014/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04069.html
  13. http://web.archive.org/web/20110612010701/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04070.html
  14. http://web.archive.org/web/20110612003540/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04072.html
  15. http://web.archive.org/web/20110612005229/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04073.html
  16. http://web.archive.org/web/20110610153117/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04074.html
  17. http://web.archive.org/web/20110612010555/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04077.html
  18. http://web.archive.org/web/20110612001918/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04079.html
  19. http://web.archive.org/web/20110612005244/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04080.html
  20. http://web.archive.org/web/20110612005249/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04268.html
  21. http://web.archive.org/web/20110612010626/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04269.html
  22. http://web.archive.org/web/20110612000853/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04272.html
  23. http://web.archive.org/web/20110612010514/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04273.html
  24. http://web.archive.org/web/20110612002235/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04290.html

Dynamics And Logic • Inquiry List 2004

  1. http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001400.html
  2. http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001401.html
  3. http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001402.html
  4. http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001403.html
  5. http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001404.html
  6. http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001405.html
  7. http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001406.html
  8. http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001407.html
  9. http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001408.html
  10. http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001410.html
  11. http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001411.html
  12. http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001412.html
  13. http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001413.html
  14. http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001415.html
  15. http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001416.html
  16. http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001418.html
  17. http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001419.html
  18. http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001420.html
  19. http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001421.html
  20. http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001422.html
  21. http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001423.html
  22. http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001424.html
  23. http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-July/001685.html
  24. http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-July/001686.html
  25. http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-July/001687.html
  26. http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-July/001688.html

Dynamics And Logic • NKS Forum 2004

  1. http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1282#post1282
  2. http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1285#post1285
  3. http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1289#post1289
  4. http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1292#post1292
  5. http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1293#post1293
  6. http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1294#post1294
  7. http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1296#post1296
  8. http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1299#post1299
  9. http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1301#post1301
  10. http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1304#post1304
  11. http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1307#post1307
  12. http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1309#post1309
  13. http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1311#post1311
  14. http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1314#post1314
  15. http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1315#post1315
  16. http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1318#post1318
  17. http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1321#post1321
  18. http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1323#post1323
  19. http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1326#post1326
  20. http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1327#post1327
  21. http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1330#post1330
  22. http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1331#post1331
  23. http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1598#post1598
  24. http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1601#post1601
  25. http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1602#post1602
  26. http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1603#post1603