Difference between revisions of "Talk:Introduction to Inquiry Driven Systems"

MyWikiBiz, Author Your Legacy — Wednesday December 25, 2024
Jump to navigationJump to search
Line 8: Line 8:
 
In order to get a handle on the space of higher order propositions and eventually to carry out a functional approach to quantification theory, it serves to construct some specialized tools.  Specifically, I define a higher order operator Υ, called the "umpire operator", which takes up to three propositions as arguments and returns a single truth value as the result.  Formally, this so-called "multi-grade" property of Υ can be expressed as a union of function types, in the following manner:
 
In order to get a handle on the space of higher order propositions and eventually to carry out a functional approach to quantification theory, it serves to construct some specialized tools.  Specifically, I define a higher order operator Υ, called the "umpire operator", which takes up to three propositions as arguments and returns a single truth value as the result.  Formally, this so-called "multi-grade" property of Υ can be expressed as a union of function types, in the following manner:
  
: &Upsilon; : <font size="+4">&cup;</font><sup>(m = 1, 2, 3)</sup> (('''B'''<sup>''k''</sup> &rarr; '''B''')<sup>''m''</sup> &rarr; '''B''').
+
<blockquote>
 +
&Upsilon; : <font face="courier new" size="+1">&cup;</font><sup>(m = 1, 2, 3)</sup> (('''B'''<sup>''k''</sup> &rarr; '''B''')<sup>''m''</sup> &rarr; '''B''').
 +
<br>
 +
</blockquote>
  
 
In contexts of application the intended sense can be discerned by the number of arguments that actually appear in the argument list.  Often, the first and last arguments appear as indices, the one in the middle being treated as the main argument while the other two arguments serve to modify the sense of the operation in question.  Thus, we have the following forms:
 
In contexts of application the intended sense can be discerned by the number of arguments that actually appear in the argument list.  Often, the first and last arguments appear as indices, the one in the middle being treated as the main argument while the other two arguments serve to modify the sense of the operation in question.  Thus, we have the following forms:

Revision as of 13:44, 17 May 2007

Notes & Queries

Jon Awbrey 06:30, 17 May 2007 (PDT)

TeX Test

Umpire Operators : HTML

In order to get a handle on the space of higher order propositions and eventually to carry out a functional approach to quantification theory, it serves to construct some specialized tools. Specifically, I define a higher order operator Υ, called the "umpire operator", which takes up to three propositions as arguments and returns a single truth value as the result. Formally, this so-called "multi-grade" property of Υ can be expressed as a union of function types, in the following manner:

Υ : (m = 1, 2, 3) ((BkB)mB).

In contexts of application the intended sense can be discerned by the number of arguments that actually appear in the argument list. Often, the first and last arguments appear as indices, the one in the middle being treated as the main argument while the other two arguments serve to modify the sense of the operation in question. Thus, we have the following forms:

Υpr q = Υ(p, q, r)
Υpr : (BkB) → B

The intention of this operator is that we evaluate the proposition q on each model of the proposition p and combine the results according to the method indicated by the connective parameter r. In principle, the index r might specify any connective on as many as 2k arguments, but usually we have in mind a much simpler form of combination, most often either collective products or collective sums. By convention, each of the accessory indices p, r is assigned a default value that is understood to be in force when the corresponding argument place is left blank, specifically, the constant proposition 1 : BkB for the lower index p, and the continued conjunction or continued product operation Π for the upper index r. Taking the upper default value gives license to the following readings:

1. Υp q = Υ(p, q) = Υ(p, q, Π).
2. Υp = Υ(p, __, Π) : (BkB) → B.

This means that Υp q = 1 if and only if q holds for all models of p. In propositional terms, this is tantamount to the assertion that pq, or that _(p (q))_ = 1.

Throwing in the lower default value permits the following abbreviations:

3. Υq = Υ(q) = Υ1 q = Υ(1, q, Π).
4. Υ = Υ(1, __, Π) : (BkB) → B.

This means that Υq = 1 if and only if q holds for the whole universe of discourse in question, that is, if and only q is the constantly true proposition 1 : BkB. The ambiguities of this usage are not a problem so long as we distinguish the context of definition from the context of application and restrict all shorthand notations to the latter.

Umpire Operators : TeX

In order to get a handle on the space of higher order propositions and eventually to carry out a functional approach to quantification theory, it serves to construct some specialized tools. Specifically, I define a higher order operator Υ, called the "umpire operator", which takes up to three propositions as arguments and returns a single truth value as the result. Formally, this so-called "multi-grade" property of \(\Upsilon\!\) can be expressed as a union of function types, in the following manner:

\[\Upsilon : \cup^{m = 1, 2, 3}((\mathbb{B}^k \to \mathbb{B})^m \to \mathbb{B}).\]

In contexts of application the intended sense can be discerned by the number of arguments that actually appear in the argument list. Often, the first and last arguments appear as indices, the one in the middle being treated as the main argument while the other two arguments serve to modify the sense of the operation in question. Thus, we have the following forms:

Υpr q = Υ(p, q, r)
Υpr : (BkB) → B

The intention of this operator is that we evaluate the proposition q on each model of the proposition p and combine the results according to the method indicated by the connective parameter r. In principle, the index r might specify any connective on as many as 2k arguments, but usually we have in mind a much simpler form of combination, most often either collective products or collective sums. By convention, each of the accessory indices p, r is assigned a default value that is understood to be in force when the corresponding argument place is left blank, specifically, the constant proposition 1 : BkB for the lower index p, and the continued conjunction or continued product operation Π for the upper index r. Taking the upper default value gives license to the following readings:

1. Υp q = Υ(p, q) = Υ(p, q, Π).
2. Υp = Υ(p, __, Π) : (BkB) → B.

This means that Υp q = 1 if and only if q holds for all models of p. In propositional terms, this is tantamount to the assertion that pq, or that _(p (q))_ = 1.

Throwing in the lower default value permits the following abbreviations:

3. Υq = Υ(q) = Υ1 q = Υ(1, q, Π).
4. Υ = Υ(1, __, Π) : (BkB) → B.

This means that Υq = 1 if and only if q holds for the whole universe of discourse in question, that is, if and only q is the constantly true proposition 1 : BkB. The ambiguities of this usage are not a problem so long as we distinguish the context of definition from the context of application and restrict all shorthand notations to the latter.