Duns Scotus

MyWikiBiz, Author Your Legacy — Thursday November 14, 2024
Revision as of 10:46, 1 January 2009 by Ockham (talk | contribs)
Jump to navigationJump to search
John Duns Scotus
'Dunce'
Born [[Birth Date:=1265|1265]]
England
Died [[Death Date:=1308|1308]]
[[Death_City:=Cologne|Cologne]], Germany
unknown
Occupation Philosopher
Contact {{{contact}}}


The blessed John Duns Scotus (Iohannes Duns Scotus OFM, Jean Duns Scot, Giovanni Duns Scoto, Johannes Duns Skotus, Juan Duns Escoto, Iohannes Dunstonensis, Iohannes Scotus, John the Scot) , was one of the most important theologians and philosophers of the High Middle Ages (the others being Thomas Aquinas, William of Ockham and Bonaventura. He was nicknamed Doctor Subtilis for his penetrating and subtle manner of thought.

Scotus' influence on Roman Catholic thought has been considerable. The doctrines for which he is best known are the univocity of being (that existence is the most abstract concept we have, applicable to everything that exists), the formal distinction, a way of distinguishing between different aspects of the same thing, and the idea of haecceity, a property supposed to be in each individual thing that makes it an individual. Scotus also developed a complex argument for the existence of God, and argued for the Immaculate conception of Mary.

Life

Little is known of Scotus' life. He was probably born at Duns, in the Borders. In 1291 he was ordained in Northampton, England. A note in Codex 66 of Merton College, Oxford, records that Scotus "flourished at Cambridge, Oxford and Paris[1]. He began lecturing on Peter Lombard's Sentences at the prestigious University of Paris in the Autumn of 1302. Later in that academic year, however, he was expelled from the University of Paris for siding with then Pope Boniface VIII in his feud with Philip the Fair of France, over the taxation of church property.

Scotus was back in Paris before the end of 1304, probably returning in May. He continued lecturing there until, for reasons which are still mysterious, he was dispatched to the Franciscan studium at Cologne, probably in October 1307. He died there in 1308; the date of his death is traditionally given as 8 November.

He is buried in the Church of the Minorites in Cologne. His sarcophagus bears the Latin inscription: Scotia me genuit. Anglia me suscepit. Gallia me docuit. Colonia me tenet. (trans. "Scotia brought me forth. England sustained me. France taught me. Cologne holds me.") He was beatified by Pope John Paul II on March 20, 1993. According to an old tradition, Scotus was buried alive following his lapse into a coma.

Work

Realism

Scotus is generally considered to be a realist (as opposed to a nominalist) in that he treated universals as real. He attacks a position close to that later defended by Ockham, arguing that things have a common nature - for example the humanity common to both Socrates and Plato.

Univocity of Being

He followed Aristotle in asserting that the subject matter of metaphysics is "being qua being" (ens inquantum ens). Being in general (ens in communi), as an univocal notion, was for him the first object of the intellect. Metaphysics includes the study of the transcendentals, so called because they transcend the division of being into finite and infinite and the further division of finite being into the ten Aristotelian categories. Being itself is a transcendental, and so are the "attributes" of being — "one", "true", and "good" — which are coextensive with being, but which each add something to it.

The doctrine of the univocity of being implies the denial of any real distinction between essence and existence. Aquinas had argued that in all finite being (i.e. all except God), the essence of a thing is distinct from its existence. Scotus rejected the distinction. We can conceive of what is is to be something, without conceiving it as existing. Scotus denied this. We should not make any distinction between whether a thing exists (si est) and what it is (quid est), for we never know whether something exists, unless we have some concept of what we know to exist [2]

Categories

The study of the Aristotelian categories belongs to metaphysics insofar as the categories, or the things falling under them, are studied as beings. (If they are studied as concepts, they belong instead to the logician.) There are exactly ten categories, according to orthodox Aristotelianism. The first and most important is the category of substance. Substances are beings in a primary sense, since they have an independent existence (entia per se). Beings in any of the other nine categories, called accidents, exist in substances. The nine categories of accidents are quantity, quality, relation, action, passion, place, time, position, and state (or habitus).

Individuation

Duns elaborates a distinct view on hylomorphism, with three important strong theses that differentiate him. He held: 1) that there exists matter that has no form whatsoever, or prime matter, as the stuff underlying all change, against Aquinas (cf. his Quaestiones in Metaphysicam 7, q. 5; Lectura 2, d. 12, q. un.), 2) that not all created substances are composites of form and matter (cf. Lectura 2, d. 12, q. un., n. 55), that is, that purely spiritual substances do exist, and 3) that one and the same substance can have more than one substantial form — for instance, humans have at least two substantial forms, the soul and the form of the body (forma corporeitas) (cf. Ordinatio 4, d. 11, q. 3, n. 54). He argued for an original principle of individuation (cf. Ordinatio 2, d. 3, pars 1, qq. 1-6), the "haecceity" as the ultimate unity of a unique individual (haecceitas, an entity's 'thisness'), as opposed to the common nature (natura communis), feature existing in any number of individuals. For Scotus, the axiom stating that only the individual exists is a dominating principle of the understanding of reality. For the apprehension of individuals, an intuitive cognition is required, which gives us the present existence or the non-existence of an individual, as opposed to abstract cognition. Thus the human soul, in its separated state from the body, will be capable of knowing the spiritual intuitively.

Formal distinction

Like other realist philosophers of the period (such as Aquinas and Henry of Ghent, Scotus recognised the need for an intermediate distinction that was not merely conceptual, but not fully real or mind-dependent either. Scotus argued for an formal distinction (distinctio formalis a parte rei), which holds between entities which are inseparable and indistinct in reality, but whose definitions are not identical. For example, the personal properties of the Trinity are formally distinct from the Divine essence. Similarly, the distinction between the 'thisness' or haecceity of a thing is intermediate between a real and a conceptual distinction[3]. There is also a formal distinction between the divine attributes and the powers of the soul.

Voluntarism

Scotus was an Augustinian theologian. He is usually associated with voluntarism, the tendency to emphasize God's will and human freedom in all philosophical issues. The main difference between Aquinas' rational theology and that of Scotus' is that Scotus believes certain predicates may be applied univocally — with exactly the same meaning — to God and creatures, whereas Aquinas insisted that this is impossible, and that only analogical predication can be employed, in which a word as applied to God has a meaning different from, although related to, the meaning of that same word as applied to creatures. Duns struggled throughout his works in demonstrating his univocity theory against Aquinas' analogy doctrine.

Existence of God

The existence of God can be proven only a posteriori, through its effects. The Causal Argument he gives for the existence of God is particularly interesting and precise. It says that an infinity of things that are essentially ordered is impossible, as the totality of caused things that are essentially caused is itself caused, and so it is caused by some cause which is not a part of the totality, for then it would be the cause of itself; for the whole totality of dependent things is dependent, and not on anything belonging to that totality. The argument is relevant for Scotus' conception of metaphysical inquiry into being by searching the ways into which beings relate to each other.

Immaculate Conception

Perhaps the most influential point of Duns Scotus' theology was his defense of the Immaculate Conception of Mary. At the time, there was a great deal of argument about the subject. The general opinion was that it was appropriate, but it could not be seen how to resolve the problem that only with Christ's death would the stain of original sin be removed. The great philosophers and theologians of the West were divided on the subject (indeed, it appears that even Thomas Aquinas sided with those who denied the doctrine, though some Thomists dispute this). The feast day had existed in the East since the seventh century and had been introduced in several dioceses in the West as well, even though the philosophical basis was lacking. Citing Anselm of Canterbury's principle, "potuit, decuit, ergo fecit" (God could do it, it was appropriate, therefore he did it), Duns Scotus devised the following argument: Mary was in need of redemption like all other human beings, but through the merits of Jesus' crucifixion, given in advance, she was conceived without the stain of original sin. God could have brought it about (1) that she was never in origin sin, (2) she was in sin only for an instant, (3) she was in sin for a period of time, being purged at the last instant. Whatever of these was more excellent should probably be attributed to Mary [4]. This apparently careful statement provoked a storm of opposition at Paris, and suggested the line 'fired France for Mary without spot' in the famous poem "Duns Scotus's Oxford", by Gerard Manley Hopkins.

This argument appears in Pope Pius IX's declaration of the dogma of the Immaculate Conception. Pope John XXIII recommended the reading of Duns Scotus' theology to modern theology students.

Logic

The authenticity of Scotus' logical works has been questioned. Some of the logical and metaphysical works originally attributed to him are now known to be by other authors. There were already concerns about this within two centuries of his death, when the sixteenth-century logician Jacobus Naveros noted inconsistencies between these texts and his commentary on the Sentences, leading him to doubt whether he had written any logical works at all [5]. The Questions on the Prior Analytics (In Librum Priorum Analyticorum Aristotelis Quaestiones) were also discovered to be mistakenly attributed [6].

Modern editors have identified only four works as authentic: the commentaries on Porphyry's Isagoge, on Aristotle's Categories, On Interpretation (in two different versions), and on Sophistical Refutations, probably written in that order. These are called the parva logicalia. These are dated at around 1295, when Scotus would have been in his late twenties, working in Oxford.

Influence

Scotus is considered one of the most important Franciscan theologians.

Primary sources

manuscripts

  • Pseudo Joh. Duns Scotus: Tractatus de Formalitatibus, Strasbourg, Bibl. Nat. & Univ. 292 (an. 1475)
  • Notabilia Scoti in Libros Topicorum:>> see article of Andrews (1998) in bibliography below
  • For an overview of manuscripts, see first of all the introductions to the latest edition of Scotus’ Opera Omnia.

editions

  • Opera Omnia, ed. Lucas Wadding, 12 Vols (Lyon: Durand, 1639; Reprint by G. Olms, Hildesheim, 1968-1968)
  • Opera Omnia, ed. L. Vives, 26 Vols. (Paris, 1891-1895; Reprint by Westmead, Franborough and Hants: Gregg International Publishers, 1969).
  • Opera Omnia, studio et cura Commissionis Scotisticae ad fidem codicum edita. XXI Vols, ed. C. Balic, H. Schalück, P. Modric et al. (Vatican City, 1950- ). The following volumes of this new critical edition of Scotus’ theological works have appeared so far:
    • Vol. 1: De Ordinatio I. Duns Scoti disquisitio historico-critica, Ordinatio, prologus, edited by C. Balic, M. Bodewig, S. Buselic, P. Capkun-Delic, I. Juric, I. Montalverne, S. Nanni, B. Pergamo, F.Prezioso, I. Reinhold, and O. Schäfer (Città del Vaticano: Typis Polyglottis Vaticanis, 1950).
    • Vol. 2: Ordinatio I, dist. 1–2, edited by C. Balic, M. Bodewig, S. Buselic, P. Capkun-Delic, I. Juric, I. Montalverne, S. Nanni, B. Pergamo, F. Prezioso, I. Reinhold, and O. Schäfer (Città delVaticano: Typis Polyglottis Vaticanis, 1950).
    • Vol. 3: Ordinatio I, dist. 3, edited by C. Balic, M. Bodewig, S. Buselic, P. Capkun-Delic, B. Hechich, I. Juric, B. Korosak, L. Modric, I. Montalverne, S. Nanni, B. Pergamo, F. Prezioso, I. Reinhold, and O. Schäfer (Città del Vaticano: Typis Polyglottis Vaticanis,1954).
    • Vol. 4: Ordinatio I, dist. 4–10, edited by C. Balic, M. Bodewig, S. Buselic, P. Capkun-Delic, B. Hechich, I. Juric, B. Korosak, L. Modric, S. Nanni, I. Reinhold, and O. Schäfer (Città del Vaticano:Typis Polyglottis Vaticanis, 1956).
    • Vol. 5: Ordinatio I, dist. 11–25, edited by C. Balic, M. Bodewig, S. Buselic, P. Capkun-Delic, B. Hechich, I. Juric, B. Korosak, L. Modric, S. Nanni, I. Reinhold, and O. Schäfer (Città del Vaticano:Typis Polyglottis Vaticanis, 1959).
    • Vol. 6: Ordinatio I, dist. 26–48, edited by C. Balic, M. Bodewig, S. Buselic, P. Capkun-Delic, B. Hechich, I. Juric, B. Korosak, L. Modric, S. Nanni, I. Reinhold, and O. Schäfer (Città del Vaticano:Typis Polyglottis Vaticanis, 1963).
    • Vol. 7: Ordinatio II, dist. 1–3, edited by C. Balic, C. Barbaric, S. Buselic, B. Hechich, L. Modric, S. Nanni, R. Rosini, S. Ruiz de Loizaga, and C. Saco Alarcón (Città del Vaticano: Typis Polyglottis Vaticanis, 1973).
    • Vol. 8: Ordinatio II, dist. 4–44, edited by B. Hechich, B. Huculak, J. Percan, and S. Ruiz de Loizaga (Città del Vaticano: Typis Vaticanis, 2006).
    • Vol. 9: Ordinatio III, dist. 1–17, edited by B. Hechich, B. Huculak, J.Percan, and S. Ruiz de Loizaga (Città del Vaticano: Typis Vaticanis, 2006).
    • Vol. 10: Ordinatio III, dist. 26–40, edited by B. Hechich, B. Huculak, J. Percan, and S. Ruiz de Loizaga (Città del Vaticano: Typis Vaticanis, 2007).
    • Vol. 16: Lecturaprol. – I, dist. 1–7,edited by C. Balic, M. Bodewig, S. Buselic, P. Capkun-Delic, B. Hechich, I.Juric, B. Korosak, L. Modric, S. Nanni, I. Reinhold, and O. Schäfer (Città delVaticano: Typis Polyglottis Vaticanis, 1960).
    • Vol. 17: Lectura I, dist. 8–45, edited by C. Balic, C. Barbaric, S. Buselic, P. Capkun-Delic, B. Hechich, I. Juric, B.Korosak, L. Modric, S. Nanni, S. Ruiz de Loizaga, C. Saco Alarcón, and O. Schäfer (Città del Vaticano: Typis Polyglottis Vaticanis, 1966).
    • Vol. 18: Lectura II, dist. 1–6, edited by L. Modric, S. Buselic, B. Hechich, I. Juric, I. Percan, R. Rosini, S. Ruiz de Loizaga, and C. Saco Alarcón (Città del Vaticano: Typis Polyglottis Vaticanis, 1982).
    • Vol. 19: Lectura II, dist. 7–44, edited by Commissio Scotistica (Città del Vaticano: Typis Polyglottis Vaticanis,1993).
    • Vol. 20: Lectura III, dist. 1–17, edited by B. Hechich, B. Huculak, J. Percan, S. Ruiz de Loizaga, and C. Saco Alarcón (Città del Vaticano: Typis Vaticanis, 2003).
    • Vol. 21: Lectura III, dist. 18–40, edited by B. Hechich, B. Huculak, J. Percan, S. Ruiz de Loizaga, and C. Saco Alarcón (Città del Vaticano: Typis Vaticanis, 2003).
  • Opera Philosophica (numerous volumes) St. Bonaventure (St. Bonaventure, New York, 1997-2006). The following volumes have appeared:
    • B. Ioannis Duns Scotus. Quaestiones in Librum Porphyrii Isagoge; Quaestiones super Praedicamenta Aristotelis, edited by R. Andrews, G. Etzkorn, G. Gál, R. Green, T. Noone, and R. Wood, Opera Philosophica 1 (St. Bonaventure, N.Y.: The Franciscan Institute Press, 1999).
    • B. Ioannis Duns Scotus. Quaestiones in libros Perihermenias Aristotelis; Quaestiones Super Librum Elenchorum Aristotelis, edited by Robert R. Andrews, O. Bychkov, S. Ebbesen, G. Gál, R. Green, T. Noone, R. Plevano, A. Traver. Theoremata, edited by M. Dreyer, H. Möhle, and G. Krieger, Opera philosophica 2 (St. Bonaventure, N.Y.: Franciscan Institute Press; Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 2004).
    • B. Ioannis Duns Scotus. Quaestiones super libros Metaphysicorum Aristotelis, Libri I–V, edited by G. Etzkorn, R. Andrews, G. Gál, R. Green, F. Kelly, G. Marcil, T. Noone, and R. Wood, Opera Philosophica 3 (St. Bonaventure, N.Y.: The Franciscan Institute Press, 1997).
    • B. Ioannis Duns Scotus. Quaestiones super libros Metaphysicorum Aristotelis, Libri VI–IX, edited by G. Etzkorn, R. Andrews, G. Gál, R. Green, F. Kelly, G. Marcil, T. Noone, and R. Wood, Opera Philosophica 4 (St. Bonaventure, N.Y.: The Franciscan Institute Press, 1997).
    • B. Ioannis Duns Scotus. Quaestiones super secundum et tertium De anima, edited by C. Bazán, K. Emery, R. Green, T. Noone, R. Plevano, A. Traver, Opera philosophica 5 (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press; St. Bonaventure, N.Y.: Franciscan Institute Press, 2006).
  • Opera Omnia. Editio Minor, I: Opera Philosophica, ed. Giovanni Lauriola, Centro Studi Personalisti ‘Giovanni Duns Scoto’ Quaderno 11 (Bari, 1998).
  • Opera Omnia. Editio Minor, II/1: Opera Theologica, ed. Giovanni Lauriola, Centro Studi Personalisti ‘Giovanni Duns Scoto’ Quaderno 12 (Bari, 1998).
  • Opera Omnia. Editio Minor, III/1: Opera Theologica, ed. Giovanni Lauriola, Quaderni scotistici, 16 (Alberobello: Editrice AGA, 2001).
  • Giovanni Scoto. Omilia sul prologo di Giovanni, ed. M. Cristiani (Vicenza, 1987). Cf. Rivista di storia e letteraturea religiosa 24 (1988), 595-598.
  • Quodlibeta, transl. as God and creatures : the quodlibetal questions with an introduction, notes and glossary by Felix Alluntis and Allan B. Wolter. Imprint Princeton ; London : Princeton University Press, 1975. xxxiv,549p ; 25cm.

Secondary sources

  • Bos, E.P., (ed.). John Duns Scotus (1265-1308) Renewal of Philosophy. Acts of the Third Symposium organized by the Dutch Society for Medieval Philosophy Medium Aevum. Elementa, 72. Amsterdam: Rodopi, 1998.
  • Frank, W. and Wollter, A. Duns Scotus, Metaphysician, Purdue University Press, 1995.
  • Gracia, J.E. & Noone, T., A Companion to Philosophy in the Middle Ages, Blackwell 2003.
  • Grenz, Stanley J., The Named God And The Question Of Being: A Trinitarian Theo-ontology, Blackwell 2005.
  • "The Death of Blessed Scotus", according to Canon Joseph Bonello and Eman Bonnici.
  • Honderich, T., (ed.) The Oxford Companion to Philosophy, article "Duns Scotus", Oxford 1995.
  • Ingham, M.B., & Mechthild Dreyer, The Philosophical Vision of John Duns Scotus: An Introduction. Washington DC: Catholic University of America Press 2004.
  • Kretzmann,N., A. Kenny, & J. Pinborg, Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy Cambridge: 1982.
  • Vos., A. The Philosophy of John Duns Scotus. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2006.
  • Williams, Thomas, (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Duns Scotus. Cambridge University Press 2003.

Notes

  1. ^ Frank & Wollter p.5
  2. ^ Opus Oxoniense I iii 1-2, quoted in Grenz p.55
  3. ^ Honderich p. 209
  4. ^ Ordinatio III, d.3, q.1
  5. ^ Ashworth 1987
  6. ^ R.P.E. Longpre


Links

Notability

This philosopher has 18 pages in the Blackwell Companion.